NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    1/8

    Book Review

    A Critique of A. C. BhaktivedantaAuthor: K. P. Sinha

    Publisher: Punthi-Pustak, Calcutta, 1997

    ISBN: 81-86791-09-4

    The aim of this book is to discredit Srila A. C. Bhaktivedanta Swami Prabhupada'spresentation of the Vedic literature, and indirectly the Gaudiya-Vedanta viewpoint. In its

    place, the author Dr K.P. Sinha, professor of Sanskrit at Assam University, presents Neo-

    Vedanta as the complete and authoritative solution to all philosophical and hermeneuticproblems in Indian philosophy. The term 'Neo-Vedanta' refers to the loosely organised,

    relativistic system that attempts to reconcile the views of all the Indian philosophical

    schools into a single, coherent system. This system emerged primarily from the teachingsof the 19[th] century Hindu teacher Ramakrishna and others like Vivekananda and

    Radhakrishnan who popularised this trend of thought in modern Hinduism.[1] Although

    Sinha never uses the term 'Neo-Vedanta' it is unmistakably his approach.

    Sinha's book quotes two-hundred and fifty passages from Srila Prabhupada's books, taken

    primarily from his commentaries on the Bhagavad-gita and Sri Caitanya-caritamrta. In 16

    chapters organised by topic, they are subsequently addressed point by point from a Neo-Vedantic perspective. Prabhupada's positions on Brahman, monism (advaita), knowledge

    (jnana), devotion (bhakti), illusion (vivarta-vada) and various heterodox schools are

    challenged with an abundance of references to a wide range of Vedic literature, secondaryliterature and their commentaries.

    The central argument of the book is that Prabhupada has not really understood the catholicviewpoint of the Vedic literature and has consequently made many needless

    'misinterpretations and unkind remarks' against non-Vaisnava systems, particularly 'the

    Mayavadis' teachers of Advaita and Neo-Vedanta. The book's stated purpose is therefore

    'to undertake the task of pointing out those misinterpretations and giving the correct viewsof the relevant concepts of the systems concerned ... to remove the evil effects these

    misinterpretations and unkind remarks tend to create in the hearts of readers of

    Bhaktivedanta's discourses.'[2] His underlying thesis is that Srila Prabhupada's booksrepresent Vaisnava sectarianism which needs to be re-evaluated in the light of an all-

    inclusive framework.

    The nature of Sinha's own Neo-Vedanta outlook itself is clarified by viewing it in the

    context of Indian philosophical history. The last millennium has seen many debates

    between the non-personal monistic school (advaita) and the dualistic, personalistic

    (Vaisnava) schools. While all sides agree that the ultimate reality called Brahman is of onenature, the monistic school of advaita contends that it is of a non-personal nature and that

    God's personality is illusory and of secondary importance. On the other hand, each of the

    personalistic Vaisnava schools describe Brahman as the intensely personal being calledVisnu, or Krsna, having an infinity of auspicious attributes. In monism, God and the soul

    are identical, while in dualism the difference is maintained even after liberation. The

    monistic school has often enjoyed prestige as the primary Vedanta school. However,throughout history, the Vaisnava schools have attempted to demonstrate the coherency and

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    2/8

    strength of their devotional theology on the basis of Vedic literature while criticising the

    monistic two-tier theory of truth.

    In response to this rich polemical tradition, the proponents of Neo-Vedanta attempted to

    incorporate the advantages of both by artificially combining the opposing conceptions into

    a single dual-natured Brahman. Neo-Vedanta, they said, is the ultimate resolution to theadvaita-versus-Vaisnava controversy with the potential of becoming a universal

    philosophy. Neo-Vedanta was then hailed as 'a grand ideal' of religious harmony and the

    'death-knell of all fanaticism, of all persecution with the sword or with the pen'.[3] In hispreface, Sinha announces his intention to demonstrate the same ideal in the course of his

    analysis of Prabhupada's writings.

    Specifically, Sinha's Neo-Vedanta accepts both the personal and the non-personal aspects

    on equal footing in what has been described as 'a many-faceted Personal-Impersonal

    Absolute Being'. Both principles are said to coexist harmoniously like 'two sides of a coin'.

    [4] Using Ramakrishna's example, he says, 'Just as the same substance may manifest itselfas water or ice depending on the degree of temperature.'[5] Both exist with the same reality

    and validity with respect to two different frames of reference. When one aspect (the

    personal natures of God and the souls) is experienced, the other (the monistic aspect) is not,and vice-versa.[6] This system is promoted by Neo-Vedantists as the real philosophy of the

    Veda, and in its support Sinha cites both monistic and personalistic sources profusely.

    Since all of Prabhupada's writings are critiqued consistently from Sinha's perspective, it is

    useful to examine his Neo-Vedanta. The most obvious problem with Sinha's presentation is

    its mishandling of both monistic and Vaisnava texts.

    Sri Caitanya (1486-1534) of the Vaisnava tradition has been blatantly misrepresented.

    Although He accepted the reality of the monism, He clearly rejected it as an object of

    meditation, or a goal of spiritual life. Over-emphasis of the non-personal aspect covers thespiritual opulences (cid-vibhuti) of the Lord in the name of impersonalism (nirakara).[7] In

    that tradition Srila Prabhupada has faithfully rejected monism as the goal of spiritual life. In

    his critique, however, Sinha in effect pits Srila Prabhupada's views against those of SriCaitanya, whom he portrays as a Neo-Vedantist:

    ...the differences between Sankara and Sri Caitanya are very little and negligible. Hence,Sri Caitanya's ruthless criticism of Sankara should be explained as an extravagance guided

    by his strong desire to redirect men pursuing the philosophical path of knowledge to the

    emotional path of bhakti.[8]

    Sinha proceeds to misinterpret esoteric dualistic states of devotional ecstasy in Gaudiya-

    Vaisnava literature like mahabhava and prema-vilasa-vivarta as essentially non-

    personalistic experiences[9]. This attempt to support his dual-Brahman theory isunconvincing, because the Gaudiya Vedanta commentary does not even refer to an

    independent non-personal Brahman as envisaged in Neo-Vedanta. The Gaudiya school

    does, however, acknowledge a non-personal effulgence (called tejas or jyoti) restingentirely on the foundation (pratistha) of God's personality.[10] The personal feature,

    however, is exalted as the highly concentrated source of the non-personal Brahman.[11]

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    3/8

    Jiva Goswami, a contemporary follower of Sri Caitanya, however, clarifies the personalism

    of Gaudiya philosophy: 'Bhagavan is, however, the original feature of the Supreme, andBrahman is manifested at a later time from the form of Bhagavan.'[12] Gaudiya Vaisnavas

    also cite the Bhagavata Purana, which relates to us how Arjuna became aware of the non-

    personal effulgence (param jyoti) as it emanated from the personal Brahman, clarifying the

    actual relationship of these two aspects of Brahman.[13] Therefore, Sinha's presentation ofSri Caitanya and His followers as Neo-Vedantists is misleading.

    Sankara (788 ce), founder of the monistic (advaita) school, has also been utterlymisrepresented by Sinha, He states, 'The philosophy of Sankara has two currents: When he

    speaks strictly as a philosopher, he points his attention to the formless and qualityless

    Brahman ... when he speaks as a devotee, he directs his attention to the divine beauty of ...the emotional Absolute. All this clearly shows that Sankara accepts the existence of

    Purusottam Krsna, the Personal Absolute'.[14] This sort of mispresentation of the monism

    of Sankara by other Neo-Vedantists has drawn severe criticism from the Dvaita scholar

    B.N.K. Sharma, whose comments are equally applicable to Sinha's presentation:

    This picture is however far from being correct or true to Sankara's own clear

    pronouncements in his Brahma-sutra-bhasya, or even logically consistent. Sankara'spronouncements on the status of Saguna and Nirguna Brahmans and the factual existence

    of the world ... give no support to any of the articles of faith of 'Neo-Vedanta' [in which] the

    Saguna and Nirguna Brahmans have been placed on the same par as the two sides of thesame coin having the same reality and validity. After crying down [Sankara's] two-tier

    theory of truth, it is a surreptitious way of introducing it again by way of 'different frames

    of reference'.[15]

    The idea of the Savisesa [personal] and Nirvisesa [non-personal] Brahman both having the

    same reality and validity as the two sides of the same coin or the vast liquidity of the Ocean

    and the solid icebergs in another part has been severely criticised by Sankara under hisVedanta commentary 2.1.14 (na canekatmakam). He argues that the Supreme Brahman can

    never be anekatmakam (double-sided) like the coin with two sides (as Neo-Vedanta wants

    us to believe). Sankara thunders, 'Nonduality will have nothing to do with accommodatingdifference of states of experience of Saguna and Nirguna from different frames of reference

    at any time in its being'(2.1.14). 'Brahman cannot be intrinsically double-natured (na svata

    eva anekatmakam) as the two natures are diametrically opposed to each other (virodha)...'Lastly, the Upanisadic thesis of ekavijnanena satvavijnanam (knowing the many by

    knowing the One) will be disproved and falsified, if it were true that when the one [aspect

    of Brahman] is known the other is not.[16]

    Indeed, Sankara unambiguously denies a dual-natured Brahman and condemns the

    devotional relation:

    Brahman must be held to be altogether without form, not at the same time of an opposite

    nature ... Brahman does not possess double characteristics although it is connected withlimiting adjuncts. Nor is it possible that Brahman should possess double characteristics 'on

    account of place'. ... If the conception of duality is once uprooted by the conception of

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    4/8

    absolute unity, it cannot arise again, and so [it can] no longer be the cause of Brahman

    being looked upon as the complementary object of injunctions of devotion.[17]

    It should also be noted that Sankara and the monists teach the unique doctrine of

    illusionism (mithyatva) that, strictly speaking, regards the world and individuality as

    completely illusory, or non-existent. Neo-Vedanta, however, while liberally using thelanguage of the monists, sees them as merely temporary.[18] This dilution of illusionism

    from indicating unreality to a transient reality clearly signals a departure from classical

    monistic metaphysics of Advaita.

    Also common in the book is his frequent appeal to Sankara's discussion in Vedanta-sutra

    4.4.12 about how a liberated soul can animate several bodies at once or live without a body.Using this, Sinha tries to prove that Advaita philosophy accommodates his dual-natured

    liberation and Brahman theory.[19] However, it is clear from context that those 'bodies'

    exist not in spiritual perfection but only in the lower illusory (vyavaharika) state of monistic

    philosophy.[20]

    Sinha's critique also fails to recognise the partial Vaisnava character of even Sankara's

    major commentaries by proposing that the deities Kali and Siva are also complete aspectsof Brahman, in addition to Visnu. However, in his unquestionably authentic works, Sankara

    only identifies God (isvara) as Visnu, rather than as any other deity. In his Gita

    commentary (13.2), isvara is identified with Visnu: isvarasya visnoh. Another identificationoccurs in Vedanta-sutra 2.2.42, where he accepts the Pancaratra teaching that Narayana is

    'higher than the undeveloped, the highest Self and the Self of all' and is the source of

    innumerable expansions. (See also similar acknowledgements in his comments to Vedanta-sutra 1.4.1, 1.4.3 and Gita 15.6.) The same idea is repeatedly expressed in his exaltation of

    Visnu's abode as the pure highest place (paramam padam) and as the end of the spiritual

    journey.[21] Even his commentary to the Svetasvatara Upanisad, with its usage of the

    names 'Siva' and 'Hara', does not make any identification of Isvara with the deity Siva.Furthermore, in his Vedanta commentary, Sankara refutes certain concepts of ancient

    Pasupata (Saiva) schools. Therefore, Sinha's presentation of Sankara acknowledging an

    equality of various deities is misleading.

    In summary, Sinha's approach is wrong and disingenuous, as it puts Adi Sankara and hisfollowers against each other on many fundamental issues. The integrity of Sinha's approach

    to Sankara, therefore, collapses in light of the foregoing evidences of his clearly monistic

    position.

    Not only is Sinha's presentation of other acaryas inaccurate, but his Neo-Vedanta

    philosophy itself has certain problems. He frequently states that upon liberation, the soul

    'may merge into the body of the Absolute.'[22] Specifically, this concept of 'merging' or theliteral dissolution of one's identity into the non-personal Brahman closely resembles, as

    noted insightfully by B.N.K. Sharma, that of ancient philosophy of bhedabheda. This

    doctrine of 'difference non-difference' was rejected by all the Vedanta schools.[23]While Vaisnava schools accept difference (bheda) and only a relative oneness (abheda) or

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    5/8

    similarity between the soul and God, this bhedabheda doctrine calls for an absolute oneness

    and difference, as does Neo-Vedanta.

    Specifically, the classical bhedabheda of Bhaskara holds that bheda and abheda are

    sequential: the initially distinct (bheda) infinitesimal soul can, upon liberation, become

    identical to the unlimited Brahman (abheda). This concept of spiritual mutability isfundamentally at odds with Vedic philosophy since it indirectly challenges the infallibility

    of Brahman by allowing for change, thereby dragging the pure Brahman conception down

    into the gutter of imperfection.[24] This has been the perennial charge against bhedabheda,and as a variant, Neo-Vedanta is also subject to the same criticism.

    In addition to this sequential view, Sinha and other Neo-Vedantists also accept both bhedaand abheda in a different sense. Sinha states the soul 'may merge into the body of the

    Absolute or may retain its individuality, according to the self's choice or liking'. Whichever

    'choice' the soul makes, both bheda and abheda are supposedly simultaneously operative in

    liberation, the terms merely reflecting differences in perspective.[25] However, this attemptto project such a dual-natured liberation theory into any Vaisnava-Vedanta is unacceptable,

    because the devotional relation (bhakti) in such a system is compromised as insubstantial

    and unreal in the monistic 'frame of reference'. This flaw is pointed out by the Dvaita-Vaisnava-Vedantist Raghunatha Tirtha (1695-1742): the bheda component of this

    bhedabheda-vada 'offers no impediment to the jiva's intuiting the blessedness of Brahman

    as his own, as [the difference] exists only in a rarefied form in the state of liberation and isas good as non-existent.'[26] Thus, bhedabheda in both variants essentially rejects bheda

    and the proper understanding of abheda, and, consequently, the bhakti relation. Therefore,

    Neo-Vedanta, as a modern form of bhedabheda is fundamentally hostile to pure devotion(bhakti) and can never be consistent with any Vaisnava-Vedanta framework.

    After refuting some salient points of variants of bhedabheda philosophy, the Sri Vaisnava

    acarya Ramanuja (1017-1137) concludes:

    Brahman becomes, on this theory, subject to the evil of conjunction with an infinite number

    of limiting conditions without any determinate localisation of effects. There is no way ofescaping this consequence. The theory is only for the consumption of believers and can

    withstand no open-minded inquiry. The wise, learned in the philosophical sciences, do not

    have any esteem for it.[27]

    He goes so far as to indicate that bhedabheda and its variations are more sinful than

    classical Advaita.[28] However that may be, Neo-Vedanta suffers from the same

    philosophical problems.

    Interestingly, Sinha's critique promotes Ramakrishna as a Vedantin, even referring to him

    rather uncritically as an incarnation (avatara) of God.[29] Jeffrey J. Kripal's intriguing workKali's Child: The Mystical and The Erotic in the Life and Teachings of Ramakrishna

    deconstructs the Ramakrishna myth revealing little more than an unorthodox tantric

    sexuality at the basis of his life, sayings, practices, and even literary styles of hisbiographers.[30] In both the Tantra traditions and Neo-Vedanta, the Brahman conception

    suffers from spiritual mutability since both traditions maintain real individual can literally

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    6/8

    dissolve its identity into a monistic perfection, as in the bhedabheda doctrine. For whatever

    reason, Ramakrishna, Vivekananda and modern proponents like Sinha have never botheredto address standing objections as they re-introduced the concept of spiritual mutability.

    Using his Neo-Vedantic prism, Sinha quotes and interprets passages of Pancaratra literature

    to support his concept of dual-Brahman. However, not only does Vaisnava personalismcandidly dominate the Pancaratra literature, but even terms like nirguna and sayujya,

    commonly understood monistically, are defined in the Vaisnava sense: 'Because [Brahman]

    has no contact with any ordinary qualities, it is called nirguna. Listen, Narada, to the six[transcendental] qualities.'[31] 'He who has become attached to the jewel of gems

    (maniratna, the kaustubha) is said to have attained identity with the Lord' (Visnu-tilaka

    2.45).[32] 'Just as gold in the midst of fire shines separately as though it were not in contact(with the fire), even so he who is clinging to Brahman (Brahman-lagna) is seen to exist in

    the form of a gem (mani)' (Visnu-tilaka 2.30). In the Padma-tantra (1.4.14-15), this very

    issue is addressed: 'What is the difference, O Highest Spirit, between Thee and the liberated

    soul?' The answer, starting off with a monistic flavour, says, 'They (the liberated) become"I". There is no difference whatsoever,' but ends by affirming plurality in perfection: 'As I

    live (viharami), just so live the liberated souls.'[33] Such passages affirm the Vaisnava

    character of even the apparently monistic statements of the Pancaratra.

    In section thirteen, Sinha criticises Srila Prabhupada's explanation of the spiritual nature of

    Lord Krsna's body. Specifically, Sinha suggests that at the time of descent into this world,the transcendental body of the Lord becomes embodied in a visually similar body of flesh

    and blood. This interpretation is specifically rejected by Vaisnava Vedantists, because it

    relies on an inapplicable and mundane interpretation of 'sambhavami' (literally, 'I takebirth') of Bhagavad-gita 4.6. Even Sankaracarya, who ultimately rejects all material and

    spiritual form as illusory, explains the word in the proper way: 'I appear to become

    embodied (dehavan iva), as though born (jata iva); ... but not in reality (na paramarthato)

    like an ordinary man (lokavat).'[34] Similarly, another famous Advaitin, Sri MadhusudanaSarasvati, explicitly states that Lord Krsna's body is made of eternity, knowledge and bliss

    (sac-cid-ananda-ghana) and is manifested (avirbhavah) even at the time of His birth

    (janmakale) (4.6, 7.24).[35] Interestingly, S. Radhakrishnan, another Neo-Vedantist,recognizing this classical interpretation, rejected it as 'unsatisfactory', offering the same

    mundane explanation of Krsna's which is repeated by Sinha.

    Throughout his book, Sinha claims to champion the cause of pure non-sectarian Vedanta,

    but even this claim is thrown into question in his concluding sections (chapters 14-16)

    which attempt to harmonise non-Vedic doctrines with Vedanta. For example, the

    materialistic philosophy of Carvaka is presented as respectable and conducive to moralityand social harmony, despite clear pronouncements by Lord Krsna to the contrary in

    Bhagavad-gita (16.8).[36] Then he presents and accedes to Buddhist arguments against

    Vedanta. One such concession is the denial of the eternality of the Veda in its linguisticformat.[37] The universally accepted Vedanta viewpoint, however, is expressed in the

    Brahmanda Purana: 'The Vedas are eternal, in their entirety; are enduring, and present in

    the mind of Visnu; at creation after creation, they are brought up as they are; with the sameorder, same characters, and the same notes, never otherwise.'[38] Sinha also defends the

    Buddhist contention that their state of perfection (sunya) is not merely an absolute void, but

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    7/8

    a state of positive bliss. However, this overlooks the fact that the Buddhist definition of

    sunya and Vedantic definition of asat (non-existence) are, in fact, similar.[39] Sinha alsoaccepts their view that the absolute truth lies midway between nihilism (sunyavada) and

    eternalism (sasvatavada) and, inaccurately, concludes that this final state is consistent with

    Brahman realisation of Advaita. Thus, the philosophy of Sinha, like those of Ramakrishna

    and other Neo-Vedantists before him, ultimately accomodates materialism, impersonality,personality, nihilistic void, and anything and everything else all in one relativistic

    system.

    Ravindra-svarupa Dasa sums up the substance of Neo-Vedanta:

    Those who have adopted traditional Advaita Vedanta to modern sorts of relativism haveintroduced a change that we should note carefully. ... The thinkers who have 'deepened'

    Sankaracarya's relativism have done away with an established illusion. No specific

    revelation carries universal authority, even provisionally. As I once heard a college girl say,

    expressing the popular rendition of this 'deepening': 'If you believe it's true, it's true foryou.' Thus the modern, deracinated individual becomes the author of reality, of creation. He

    is now set free to believe in everything whatsoever precisely because he believes in nothing

    at all.[40]

    Sinha's major criticism of Prabhupada's supposed misrepresentation of others has several

    other bases. One possible source is that Srila Prabhupada uses the term 'Mayavada' broadlyto refer to both classical monism of Sankara as well as Neo-Vedanta, since both see illusion

    (maya) as a relatively independent principle. Therefore, each of his criticisms of

    'Mayavada' do not necessarily apply to both types. Another possible source is how SrilaPrabhupada not only criticises the face-value of monism but also for what is, in his view, its

    logical extensions and indirect results like materialism.[41] In fact, the Bhagavad-gita

    (12.5) affirms the relative difficulty of meditation on the non-personal aura of Brahman,

    and the failure in this path naturally results in materialism. Another cause of misgivings isSrila Prabhupada's writing style, which is spiced with humour, sarcasm, and contemporary

    socio-religious criticism. In particular, his sharp remarks against very reputable

    philosophical opponents like Sankara, Vivekananda, and Radhakrishnan are criticised bySinha as 'unparliamentary'.[42] However, when seen in context, these remarks shatter the

    sentimentalism of secular religion and provoke analytical thought in his readers. It should

    be noted that Srila Prabhupada was personally very respectful to all his opponents includingRadhakrishnan.

    Sinha validly notes several minor points in Srila Prabhupada's books. One is the latter's

    reference to Sankara as equating Lord Sankarsana with the individual soul (jiva) in hisVedanta-sutra 2.2.42 commentary.[43] Although Sankara here draws no equation between

    the two alternate referents, it is a natural conclusion of monism and Srila Prabhupada's

    ensuing argument against this conclusion is generally applicable. In another case, thedefinitions of vikara and vivarta used to explain the theory of transformation (parinama-

    vada) is incorrectly attributed to the Vedanta-sutra. However, these definitions are general

    and accepted by all Vedanta schools, and therefore Srila Prabhupada's use of them is valid.[44] These instances do not detract from Srila Prabhupada's overall presentation of the

    Vaisnava viewpoint.

  • 7/27/2019 NeoVedantino Ataca Prabhupada

    8/8

    In summary, Sinha's critique of Srila Prabhupada's works amounts to a presentation of therelativistic Neo-Vedanta outlook with its underlying hostility towards the fundamental truth

    of bhakti as well as Vedanta. Although he ambitiously cites an impressive array of Vedic

    and Saivite texts, he disingenuously invokes the names of Sankaracarya and Sri Caitanya to

    support his philosophy and, like others before him, fails to address the universal objectionsto spiritual mutability. Nevertheless, this Neo-Vedantic challenge to Vaisnavism will be of

    interest to ISKCON devotees currently involved in dialogue with adherents of modern

    Hindu philosophy.