Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    1/6

    1

    Bryn Mawr Classical Review 03.02.03

    Anton F. Harald Bierl,Dionysos und die griechische Tragdie.Politische und "metatheatralische" Aspekte im Text. Classica

    Monacensia 1. Tbingen: Gunter Narr Verlag, 1991. Pp. xii +

    298. ISBN 3-8233-4861-2.

    Reviewed by Thomas Marier, The Johns Hopkins University.

    B.'s purpose is to ascertain the "functions" of Dionysus in tragedy as it was

    experienced by the fifth-century Athenian audience (2). The influence ofGerman reception theory is evident in his orientation, though not in his

    bibliography. Thus, to assess the audience's response to references to

    Dionysus, B. undertakes to recover the Athenians' understanding of the god,

    the "horizon" of their expectations with respect to him (21, 27, 147). The

    Athenians thought of Dionysus as the god of wine, maenadism, and the

    afterlife; B. argues that he was also regarded as a god of politics and the

    theater -- indeed, these were his foremost provinces, at least during the

    dramatic performances of the last third of the fifth century (220).

    Yet for the Athenians, in B.'s view, Dionysus was not just a god whose

    domain included all these disparate phenomena; he also had an essence thatinhered in all of them. According to B.'s "maxim of interpretation" (128),

    that essence was ambivalence. Dionysus spanned pairs of opposing qualities

    such as life and death, peace and war, polis and wilderness. B. arrives at this

    essence by an avowedly structuralist procedure: he lumps together all

    available data pertaining to the god, contrives oppositions from these data,

    and asserts that the relation of ambivalence between these oppositions was

    the god's quiddity. At this level of abstraction, a case could be made for the

    ambivalence of practically all gods and even heroes in tragedy. What, then,

    does ambivalence tell us about the Dionysiac? It is possible that the god was

    understood as essentially ambivalent by the Orphics who carved EIRENE

    POLEMOS and ALETHEIA PSEUDOS on bones found in Olbia on thenorthern coast of the Black Sea (15 n. 35), or that Heraclitus (22 B 15 Diels-

    Kranz) saw him as essentially ambiguous, but can we assume that the

    Athenian audience did?

    B. finds fault with those (e.g. Girard) who have emphasized the subversive

    god of myth (especially ofBacch.) virtually to the exclusion of the cohesive

    god of cult. This emphasis on the negative side of the god has given rise to

    the notion that Dionysus was non-political, that he could only oppose, but

    not be integrated into, the polis (Vidal-Naquet). B., by contrast, sees the cult

    of Dionysus as vital to the polis. The Greater Dionysia, for example,

    promoted civic solidarity (153-54 on Plato,Leg. 653c7-d5); it "unified allthe citizens into a huge, homogeneous, Dionysiac retinue" and "as it did so

    their worries and fears were dissolved in the joyous rapture of the religious

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    2/6

    2

    community" (20). Tragedy, as a part of the festival and the cult of Dionysus,

    was also vital to the polis. B. considers the "political dimension" of

    Dionysus in tragedy, adopting a line of inquiry that began with J.-P. Vernant

    (45-110). In the theater the Athenians experienced vicariously the negation

    of their own values and norms. Paradoxically, this experience made the polisstronger. By exposing the citizens to alien power structures, for example,

    tragedy made them aware of the fragility of their own democratic

    institutions. It also gave them an opportunity to deal with problems to which

    they could not address themselves in other public fora, to scrutinize their

    attitudes, to play out scenarios, to experiment.

    Various oppositions may be construed between the imaginary world of the

    plays and the real one in which the Athenians lived: present and past, inside

    and outside, self and other. B. argues that Dionysus is "the point at which

    the ambiguities that span the tragedies take definite form and from which

    their true meaning arises" (48). The god is mentioned most often in theplays that have Thebes, the antitype of Athens, as their setting (Septem, Ant.,

    OT, HF, andBacch.). In each of these plays an autocrat (Eteocles, Creon,

    Oedipus, Lycus, Pentheus) rushes blindly to his undoing. In every case B.

    attributes the autocrat's demise to his excessive rationalism. The ruler is

    punished by Dionysus, the god in whom the old, circular, theonomic way of

    thinking and the new, linear, rational one are united. For the Athenians the

    lesson to be drawn from the Theban tragedies was that the good ruler must

    not attempt to govern by reason alone but must recognize the "other" (by

    which B. seems to mean a source of transcendent authority; 64, 69).

    B. locates Dionysus on the map of tragedy, establishing a scale with which

    to measure the "degree of otherness" (222) of places where Dionysus

    appears, i.e. the extent to which they differ from Athenian norms. He puts

    positive Athens at one end of this scale, negative Thebes at the other end.

    Argos, in Euripides' Or., is close to Thebes on the scale because it is the

    scene of madness and attempted murder described in Dionysiac terms (91).

    Delphi occupies the "middle space" (92) between Athens and Thebes. InIT,

    where Euripides emphasizes the chthonic side of Dionysus (Orestes and

    Iphigeneia are rendered inactive by chthonic forces in the course of the

    play), Delphi tends towards the "negative" pole, while inPhoen. Delphi is

    portrayed as positive by the chorus of Tyrian maidens.Phoen. 226-38evokes Delphi as the panhellenic cult of Dionysus. For the Athenian

    audience this passage was felt to be "a part of the worship of Dionysus"

    because Athens sent women to Delphi every two years to take part in

    Bacchic rites as thuiades on Parnassus (99; cf. 93).

    Finally, B. looks at the two plays in which Dionysus appears in connection

    with Athens: OC, where he is situated in a locus amoenus on the periphery

    of the city (by granting asylum to Oedipus, Theseus shows his "openness to

    the other," 103), andIon, where Euripides dared to represent an Athenian

    mother plotting to kill her own son. InIon the chorus of Athenian women,

    calling on Dionysus, suggests that Ion is a theomakhos deserving to die asPentheus did, for Athens should not be ruled by a foreigner (714-717). In

    denying that Athenians participate in the revels on Parnassus, the chorus

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    3/6

    3

    "projects the wild side of Dionysus onto Delphi" (108). Athens is on the

    verge of turning into Thebes. Ultimately, however, Athena intervenes ex

    machina to set things straight. Thus, the "lesson" of this play is that the polis

    must integrate "the other, that is, the wild half of the god Dionysus" (108).

    As for Creusa's attempt on Ion's life, Euripides seems to be warning hiscontemporaries that "the democracy must uph old its values" if it is not to

    sink into the vortex of violent attack and counterattack (109).

    The evidence adduced by B. for the Athenian understanding of Dionysus as

    a preeminently political god is unfortunately far from compelling. He

    appeals to F. Kolb's "revolutionary thesis" (Agora und Theater, Volks- und

    Festversammlung[Berlin, 1981]) that in the sixth-century agora the

    orchestra was located within the sacred precinct of Dionysus Lenaeus and

    served not only as the site of early dramatic performances but also as a

    political and juridical center, and concludes that politics and the cult of

    Dionysus, of which early drama was a part, therefore formed "an indivisibleunity" at that time, and political decisions were made under the tutelage of

    "the god of the polis par excellence" and carried divine authority (51-52).

    But as R. Seaford (CR 33 [1983] 288-89) has pointed out, this thesis

    depends on dubious arguments from proximity (e.g. if the orchestra was

    near a political statue [the tyrannicides], then it must have served a political

    purpose [as a place of assembly]. Moreover, even if tragedy did have such

    ties to political activity in the sixth century, it is hazardous to build an

    argument for a fifth-century attitude on the basis of sixth-century evidence.

    During the decades that separated the the earliest extant play from the

    Peisistratid period tragedy probably changed no less extensively than did

    other Athenian institutions. The notion, also Kolb's, that the tragedians of

    the fifth century saw themselves as the successors of the priests of Dionysus

    Lenaeus, who once advised the Athenians in political matters, is just a guess

    (45). Nor can I see howIon 1074-86 and a fragment from Hermippus's

    Phormophoroi (PCG 5 fr. 63 Kassel-Austin) show that Dionysus was the

    "divine personification of Athens" (106). In the end, B. is left with the

    allegory ofFrogs, in which Dionysus is the embodiment of the theater as an

    institution of the polis (the primary purpose of which is to improve the

    citizens rather than to indulge their passion for verbal and musical

    exhibitions). In this sense he is also, I suppose, a "god of the polis."

    It is, however, one thing to say that Dionysus' theater instructed, quite

    another to say that its instruction was Dionysiac.Frogs gives no indication

    of the Dionysiac knowledge that, according to B., a polis needs to save

    itself. Here B. does not just mean that tragedy was political because for the

    Athenians it served as a medium whereby certain problems of the polis were

    publicly expressed. He means that tragedy conveyed a peculiarly Dionysiac

    "message" (e.g. 73), which seems to have been that "government founded

    on reason alone is extremely precarious, unless it succeeds in integrating the

    other." In the course of the transition from "the traditional outlook, which

    was marked by religious ideas" to "the new polis thinking that was based on

    pure rationality" the Athenians ran the risk of forgetting that they weredependent on the gods (64). Tragedy was a part of a counter-enlightenment,

    and served to remind the Athenians of this dependence. The political

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    4/6

    4

    wisdom of Dionysus lay in the recognition of the limitations of a form of

    rule that recognized no authority beyond itself (autocracy in the tragic

    fiction, democracy in fifth-century Athens). Thus, Pentheus could have

    "saved the city" by accepting Dionysus, as Athens preserved itself by

    celebrating the god's festival every year (74). It is difficult to see how thisDionysiac wisdom would have saved Thebes from the pestilence in OTor

    Heracles from the wrath of Hera inHF. Even more difficult, though, is the

    connection between this wisdom and Dionysus. B. often makes the

    connection at the expense of the text. Is Antigone the "agent" of Dionysus

    despiteAnt. 955-65, where she is likened to Lycurgus (67)? Is the condition

    of those affected by the war in Septem best described as Dionysiac mania,

    even th ough Dionysus is absent from that play?

    Turning to Dionysus in his theatrical dimension, B. asserts that every

    reference to Dionysus might have "metatragic" implications: by

    "metatragedy" B. means a species of "metatheater," which he defines as "thetotality of mechanisms whereby the poet reveals that he is aware of himself

    as the creator of drama and whereby the theater refers to itself" (116). B.

    develops a model of communication to explain how evocations of the god of

    the theater, including music, musical instruments, choral dancing, the

    Muses, Graces, Mnemosyne (Dionysus assumed the entourage of Apollo

    Mousegetes [99]), and the vocabulary of early dramatic theory (e.g.

    mechane, Helen 813, 1034), were deployed by the poets to guide the

    audience's response to dramatic events. B. is responding to O. Taplin, who

    objects to the notion of metatragedy on the ground that reflexivity always

    involves a rupture of dramatic illusion (as it regularly did in comedy). Thus,

    B. attempts to bridge the gap between the illusion or "spell" of the dramatic

    action and reflexivity; the spell, he says, was momentarily transcended, but

    never broken as it was in, say, theparabaseis of comedy. The audience's

    religious feeling (Ergriffenheit) would oscillate between the "fictive space"

    of the drama and "the real space" of the theater within the sacred precinct of

    Dionysus. The audience was perhaps conscious of the metatragic signal, but

    only "to a very small degree" (118).

    The use of Dionysiac references for this purpose presupposes a "metatragic

    consciousness" that made such communication possible. B. imagines that

    with the slackening of the ties between tragedy and the cult of Dionysus, thetragic poets grew increasingly aware of Dionysus as a theater god, at least

    during the festival, and they began to employ terms from his cult to call

    attention to the operations of the theater. The language of cult became a

    tragic "metalanguage" (120-21). Aeschylus, for example, employed the cult

    term bakkheia at Cho. 698 to prepare the audience for the murder of

    Clytemnestra (the word would have suggested a sudden reversal from joy to

    suffering).

    B. notes that in the extant works of Sophocles (124-137) Dionysus is

    mentioned explicitly only in choral songs. Here Dionysus appears as the

    cohesive god of cult. B. examines three passages from precatastrophic songsof joy (Ant. 1140-54; OT1105-9; Trach. 216-220) in which Dionysus is

    evoked as the god of festivity, music, and wine to show how the resulting

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    5/6

    5

    momentary illusion of happiness intensifies the shock of disillusionment.

    "The audience," B. says in connection with the passage fromAnt., "when

    confronted with its own cultic experience, is swept into the whirl of the

    chorus's naive expectation of a happy outcome" (132).

    Euripides (137-218) "considered the manifest connection between tragedy

    and the cult of Dionysus and accordingly made him into the supreme

    principle of drama" (138). The Euripidean chorus frequently evokes this

    principle to aid the audience in its int erpretation of the action. This is

    metatragedy in its true sense (137). If Sophocles threw light on the friendly

    god of Athenian experience, Euripides reveals him in all his ambivalence:

    the god as experienced in cult clashes openly with the imaginary god of

    myth. In his exposition of the metatragic inHF(140-46), for example, B.

    argues that Euripides intensified the effect of the reversals in this play by

    connecting Heracles with Dionysus. For "no god, to Euripides' mind, better

    expressed the change from one extreme to another than the god of tragedyhimself" (140). Thus, the first reversal (HF514) B. calls a metabole (141),

    and the second is so labelled in the text itself (735; cf. 765-66, 884). The

    word metabole is employed by Aristotle in his definition of peripety (Poet.

    1452a 22-23), which B. regards as somehow connected with Dionysus (119,

    143); he is tempted by the thought that Aristotle borrowed it from the poets,

    or at least that it belonged to a dramaturgical vocabulary that had already

    sprung up by the time ofHF(143 n. 88, 225). This word, B. thinks, signals

    metatragically the critical moment when the action is about to take a sudden

    turn (it does just that at the conclusion of the third stasimon, 815ff.). The

    mad Heracles is characterized in Dionysiac imagery (esp. 889-98, just

    before he kills his children). According to B., Heracles unites the two sides

    of Dionysus: he reflects the positive, cultic side of the god in the first half of

    the play, where he is the embodiment of Bacchic hope in the eyes of his

    loved ones, and the negative, mythical side in the second half, where he

    becomes their murderer.

    In sum, an evocation of the Dionysus in his theatrical dimension might (a)

    serve as a dramaturgical signal, a device to prepare the audience for a

    subsequent turn of events. It might (b) induce the audience to experience

    vicariously the optimism of the dramatis personae (e.g. of the chorus in

    Sophocles' plays) by calling forth the "positive" cultic context. It might (c)call attention to the operation of tragedy, especially the sudden reversal,

    which Aristotle called peripety; theatrical metalanguage (e.g. metabole [HF

    735], eleos andphrike [Phoen. 1284-87],phroimion [HF753]) can suggest

    the tragic principle of sudden reversal. Finally, it might (d) cause the

    audience to reflect on the theatrical illusion (Hel., cf. Cho., IT) or on the

    value of the theater for the polis (Bacch. does this by dramatizing, through

    the monitory example of Pentheus, the breakdown of theatrical

    communication).

    In answering Taplin's objection that metatragedy involves the rupture of

    dramatic illusion, B. proposes a highly unlikely model according to whichan evocation of Dionysus is a signal received momentarily just above the

    threshold of consciousness. However, B.'s quasi-Nietzschean notion of

  • 7/30/2019 Review A.F.H. Bierl, Dionysos Und Die Griechische Tragodie

    6/6

    6

    tragedy as a religious experience in which the individual was fused with the

    collective (20, 112; "such an experience may have been had by maenads in a

    thiasos" [cf.Bacch. 75 with Dodd's note], but was it had by the audience of

    tragedy?) precludes metatragedy of any kind: one cannot undergo loss of

    self and be self-conscious at the same time. Furthermore, B. admits that theaudience would not have been able to receive most of the signals that he has

    detected (117-18 , 147, 159, 223). If the metatragic is largely a readerly

    construct, how can he appeal to the festival as the cultic context of the

    performance, as he does, for example, in his discussion of the Dionysiac

    reference as an emotional trigger in Sophocles' choral songs?

    Having developed a model that purports to explain the maintenance of the

    dramatic spell, B. points to references that presuppose the rupture of that

    spell. Does the chorus "partly transcend its fictional role" in the third

    stasimon ofHF, where it summons the daughters of the river Asopus to

    "Heracles' glorious victory contest (787-88), referring metatragically to thecontest from which Euripides wishes, on the strength ofHF, to emerge

    victorious" (144)? Is Helen being told to take "the cult of Dionysus as a

    pattern for her subsequent conduct" inHelen 1358-68, where fawnskins, ivy,

    fennel wands, and flowing hair are mentioned (163)? Does this

    recommendation to a woman who has conceived, and is staging, an intrigue

    that requires her to cast aside her "self" suggest a connection between

    maenadism and role-playing as forms of Dionysiac ecstasy? Would this

    passage have been understood by the audience as a reflection of the nature

    of the theater (169)?

    Only by straining the texts does B. find in Dionysus the key to the political

    in tragedy, to tragic geography, to dramatic irony, to the triggering of the

    audience's emotions, or to peripety. He is looking for a previously unseen

    nexus between Dionysus and tragedy. He accuses others (Nietzsche,

    Vernant, Brelich, Goldhill) of "superimposing onto the plays criteria of

    interpretation that are external to them" (220). Oddly, he makes use of the

    ideas of these scholars (cf. especially S. Goldhill,JHS[1987] 75-76), and in

    assuming that Dionysus was a god whose essence was ambivalence, he is

    not immune to this charge himself.