Sedley- decentralisation

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    1/12

     

    CRON CHE

    ERCOL NESI

    bollettino

    del centro internazionale per

    o studio dei papiri ercolanesi

    fondato da Marcello Gigante

    33 2003

    direzione

    Graziano rrighetti

    Knut Kleve

    F rancesca Longo uricchio

    redazione

    Giovanni Indelli

    Giuliana Leone

    M CCHI ROLI EDITORE

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    2/12

    The importance of the Herculaneum papyri, and of the writings of Philode-

    mus in particular, to our understanding of late Hellenistic culture and

    thought

    is

    one which Marcello Gigante worked for most of his life to illu-

    minate. The theme of my paper

    is

    that these same texts are important in

    another and often less appreciated way. They are a symptom of, and at the

    same time an eloquent witness to, an epoch-making change

    that

    philosophy

    underwent in the 1st century C in my view, the most significant change

    to occur in the entire history of ancient philosophy, and one which divides

    that history into two radically distinct halves. n the first part of this paper,

    I shall sketch the nature of the change tha t I have in mind, with the aim of

    contextualising, and thereby understanding better, Philodemus own place

    in the history of philosophy. But I will also, wherever possible, use evidence

    from Philodemus and his library in drawing the sketch. In the second half of

    the paper, I will go on to ask how Philodemus and his work relate to one

    particular aspect of this change, one concerned with the construction of

    school histories.

    Let

    me

    interject, at this initial stage, a word about the dating of Philodemus

    books on school history. Although

    it

    remains debatable, I am going

    to

    assume the correctness of the widely held view that

    both

    the

    Index Stoicorum

    and the

    Index Academicorum

    are books from Philodemus work, in ten books

    (or possibly more), entitled

    -r v cptA.ocr6cprov

    (henceforth,

    Syntaxis ,

    whose

    tenth

    book we know to have dealt with the Epicureans. Furthermore,

    I am going to assume that the entire work belongs to a single period of

    Philodemus life, a period which, i so, cannot be dated before the 50s BC,

    since the

    Index Academicorum

    refers not only to the death of Antiochus

    in

    69, but also to the many pupils accumulated by his successor Aristus (col.

    35), presumably after succeeding to the headship. Assuming

    in

    addition that

    Philodemus died in the 30s BC, the work probably belongs to the last two to

    three decades of his life.

    A further question, which

    as

    far

    as

    I am aware has not been adequately

    addressed, is whether the

    Syntaxis

    was purely biographical, or also doxogra-

    phical. Certainly what we have of it includes no doxography, and the ten-

    dency has been to suppose

    that

    there was none. But we have only the book

    endings. What was

    in

    the lost first parts of the same rolls? n the case of the

    Stoic book, there seems to me a strong case for the conjecture that the first

    part was doxographical.

    The

    first surviving columns are

    part

    of the biogra-

    phy of the school s founder, Zeno. Yet at the end Philodemus appears to

    summarise the book s contents

    as

    having covered only the Stoics.

     

    Given the

    improbability that Zeno s biography filled well over half the book, added to

    the book s apparent concentration on the Stoics alone, I have difficulty

    imagining what filled the first half or more,

    i

    not a Stoic doxography. This

    possibility will be worth bearing in mind when we ask to what extent

    Philodemus work may have been a forerunner

    of

    Diogenes Laertius

    Lives,

    which certainly combines (albeit not

    in

    the same sequence)

    both

    doxography

    and biography.

    I confess to being less sure whether the same need apply to the

    Index Aca-

    demicorum.

    This, analogously to the Stoic book,

    is

    still engaged in the bio-

    graphy of the founder, Plato, at the point where our text begins.

    That

    31

    DAVID SEDLEY

    PHILODEMUS ND

    THE DECENTR LIS TION

    OF PHILOSOPHY

    D VID SEDLEY

    The summary might, in principle, apply not

    to the whole book, but just to its last section.

    However, that would be in contrast with the

    ending of the Index Academicorum, on which

    see below.

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    3/12

    parallelism might suggest the same conjecture, namely that the lost first part

    was

    doxographical. The difference however is that this time the book s

    ending

    indicates

    at least

    as

    I understand

    t

    that the book has covered

    not just Plato s school, the Academy, but also, prior to that, the school

    founded by Eudides, that is, the Megarics. Such a sequence

    is

    of great

    interest because

    it

    is

    identical to the sequence of di doch i found in Dio-

    genes Laertius books II-III, which once again encourages the supposition of

    a historical link between the two works. But

    it

    also means that,

    so

    far as this

    particular book of Philodemus work

    is

    concerned, we do not actually need

    the hypothesis of a doxographical component in order to fill out the missing

    earlier part. In principle, biographies of the principal Megaric and Platonic

    philosophers could have been enough to fill the book. Moreover, the philo-

    sophical heterogeneity of the Platonic school s leading adherents - includ-

    ing

    as

    they did not only Plato and his early successors,

    but

    also Arcesilaus,

    Carneades and

    Phi lo

    would have made a single consolidated doxographi-

    cal

    summary almost impossible, although a doxography divided into discrete

    phases might still have been. a possibility. These doubts mean that the

    structural homogeneity of Philodemus treatise cannot be assumed, and his

    method

    may well

    have varied according to the nature of each sect.

    Let

    me

    now turn to the radical change of which I have said

    that

    Philodemus

    and his library are both symptoms and witnesses.

    t is

    one that sprang from

    Athens loss of its status as the unchallenged centre of the philosophical

    world. Until the later part of the 2nd century BC, for Epicureans, Stoics,

    Academics and Peripatetics alike there can be no doubt that their sects

    Athenian headquarters and their resident scholarchs possessed an unques-

    tioned supremacy. Virtually

    all

    significant philosophical developments took

    place at Athens, in the very same communities which Epicurus, Zeno, Plato

    and Aristotle had founded there. Even if there may have been, for some, the

    opportunity to attend a local philosophical school in Asia Minor or else-

    where, there can be no doubt

    as

    to the massive migration of aspiring philo-

    sophy students to Athens.

    Towards the end of the 2nd century, but much more so in the early st

    century, there are signs that this Athenocentric bias

    was

    diminishing. The

    growth of Roman power and influence, along with a Roman interest in

    philosophy that had been deepening ever since the visit of three Athenian

    scholarchs to Rome in 55 BC,

    was

    beginning to make residence in Italy,

    along with the patronage of the politically powerful, a natural magnet for

    philosophers. Whenever

    we may

    date Philodemus decision to leave Athens

    for Italy,

    it is

    in an obvious

    way

    a symptom of this new shift in the centre of

    gravity.

    But even if Roman expansionism

    may

    have been the leading reason for the

    decline of Athens, Italy

    was

    not the only direction in which the exodus

    proceeded. At least some philosophers travelled east. Twoá examples may

    give

    us

    a clue as to the motivation.

    First, take the island of Rhodes. Although Panaetius

    was

    formally head of

    the Athenian Stoic school until his death in 110, his frequent absences in

    Rome may

    well

    both reflect and help account for Athens diminishing im-

    portance as a Stoic centre at this time. Posidonius, P.anaetius most distin-

    CRONACHE ERCOLANESI

    32

    á

    '

    ¥]

    v 1

     

    "'

    l

    l

    II

    \

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    4/12

    guished pupil, never became head of the Athenian school, but went to teach

    in Rhodes. Since Rhodes was Panaetius native island, but not that of Po-

    sidonius,

    it

    is a reasonable guess that Panaetius - reported to have retained

    his Rhodian citizenship and even his family s priesthood in the Rhodian

    town of Lindos, and to have refused the offer of Athenian naturalisation

    2

    - had himself already been fostering the Stoic school there

    in absentia,

    especially if as may be conjectured, he owned property on the island. To

    ll appearances, this Rhodian school in effect now eclipsed, or even replaced,

    the Athenian one. For in addition to Hecaton - another eminent Stoic of

    the day who,

    as

    a Rhodian, may be guessed to have been

    at

    least associated

    with the Rhodian school

    3

    - we can link at least two further individuals with

    it, neither of them a native Rhodian. Paramonus of Tarsus, a follower of

    Panaetius who appears in Philodemus Index

    Stoicorum

    (74, 77), seems to

    have moved to Rhodes, as has been persuasively proposed by Jean-Louis

    Ferrary on the evidence of a Rhodian statue base dedicated by him.

    4

    And

    the fully institutional character of the Rhodian school

    is

    further confirmed

    by the fact that Posidonius own grandson Jason of Nysa eventually suc-

    ceeded him

    as

    its head.

    5

    This presence in the early first-century

    BC

    Rhodian

    school of a non-Rhodian contingent is a striking feature, and suggests that

    what we are witnessing is less the decentralisation that was to become the

    hallmark of philosophy in the imperial age, than its attempted recentralisa-

    tion, to a new headquarters which at least for a while imitated the metro-

    politan role previously played by Athens.

    Although the choice of Rhodes for this role may be suspected to have

    depended at least in part on the geographical accident of Panaetius birth,

    it

    is

    perhaps no coincidence that around the same time we hear of an

    Epicurean school in Rhodes, whose members showed a degree of indepen-

    dence from the school s Athenian headquarters sufficient

    to

    shock at least

    one of the latter s adherents.

    6

    It

    was plausibly suggested by Cronert

    7

    that

    Timasagoras and Nicasicrates, two Epicureans whom Philodemus heartily

    dislikes, were leading figures of this school, both their names being Rhodian.

    But no specific name is

    attached

    to

    the Epicurean, teaching in Rhodes,

    whom Philodemus criticises in book II of his

    Rhetoric as

    defending what he

    considers an incorrect interpretation of the school founders views on rheto-

    ric. Philodemus complains that this unnamed person takes the school ortho-

    doxy to be that no rhetoric

    is

    a

    techne.

    But, Philodemus adds, the same

    person reports having heard from fellow-Epicureans recently returned from

    Athens that this

    is

    not the view held there, even though they were shock-

    ingly ill-informed as to what the textual warrant was for their alternative

    version of the school orthodoxy. What, for my present purposes, is most

    remarkable is the independence shown by the Rhodian Epicurean: when

    informed, apparently for the first time, of the doctrine on rhetoric defended

    as school orthodoxy by the current scholarch Zeno of Sidon, he proceeded to

    write a rebuttal of it. By the date of this incident, which must predate

    Zeno s death in the 70s BC, it is clear that the Athenian school s prestige

    has fallen very low indeed.

    The second example that I have in mind is Miletus. The Epicurean Deme-

    trius of Laconia, Philodemus older contemporary and author of a number of

    3 3

    DAVID SEDLEY

    2

    Panaetius fr. 10 ALESSE.

    Other known Rhodian Stoics

    of the

    same

    generation are a certain Plato (D.L. III 109),

    Stratocles (Philodemus,

    Index Stoicorum

    17)

    and possibly Leonides (Strabo XIV 2.13).

    For a valuable catalogue of philosophers as-

    sociated with Rhodes (albeit lacking Paramo-

    nus), see B. MYGIND Intellectuals in Rhodes,

    in

    V.

    GABRIELSEN et

    AL.

    (ed.), Hellenistic

    Rhodes (Aarhus 1999), pp. 247-293.

    4

    J.-L. FERRARY Philheltenisme

    et Imperia-

    lisme (Rome 1988), p. 461

    s.

    Posidonius

    T40 EDELSTEIN-KinD.

    6

    The

    evidence comes from Philodemus,

    Rhetoric II, and is presented in D SEDLEY

    Philosophical

    allegiance in

    the Greco-Roman

    world, in M T

    GRIFFIN

    and}

    BARNES (ed.),

    Philosophia

    Togata

    (Oxford 1989), pp. 97-

    119.

    7

    W CRoNERT

    Kolotes

    und

    Menedemos

    (Mu-

    nich 1906), p. 91. Cf. F. LoNGO AURICCHIO-

    A. TEPEDINO GuERRA Chi

    e

    Timasagora?, in

    Atti

    del

    convegno intemazionale La regione

    sotterrata

    dal Vesuvio: studi

    e

    prospettive

    (Na-

    ples 1979), pp. 1-9.

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    5/12

    8

    E PuGLIA Demetrio Lacone a Mileto

    ÇCEreÈ 13/1983, pp. 21-24.

    9

    The fullest discussion of these events is

    FERRARY,

    op.

    cit.,

    pp. 435-494.

    10

    Posidonius ap. Athenaeus V 213D) pre-

    sents Athenian in 88 speaking of the gymna-

    sia being in a squalid condition and the phi-

    losophical schools silent, but no causes are

    mentioned.

    Cic., Fin V 1-6.

    works preserved in Philodemus library,á seems to have settled at or near

    Miletus, as Enzo Puglia has argued.

    8

    For at the end of his treatise preserved

    in PHerc 1012 he addresses a certain Irenaeus, describing him

    as

    a philo-

    sophical colleague who has never left the beautiful city of Miletus (meaning

    either that he has literally

    never

    left it, or at any rate that he never once left

    during their extended philosophical collaboration). The reason for Deme-

    trius choice of Miletus, plausibly suggested by Puglia, makes an interesting

    parallel to the case of Posidonius. Although Demetrius himself was,

    as

    his

    title attests, a Spartan, his old teacher, Protarchus,

    was

    a native of Bargylia,

    a neighbouring city to Miletus.

    I t

    is an attractive hypothesis that Demetrius,

    like Panaetius, inherited either property or, more specifically, the headship

    of a school from his former teacher, and that the choice of geographical

    location was determined in that way

    The diaspora of which I have been speaking had certainly started before the

    crucial years

    88-86

    BC, which constitute the climax of the decentralisation

    process, and to which I shall now turn.

    9

    They were the years in which at first

    the Peripatetic Athenion and then the Epicurean Aristion briefly gained

    absolute power at Athens, both siding with Mithridates against the Romans.

    The same years

    also saw

    the events - a product of the protracted Mithri-

    datic War 89-84)- that finally destroyed Athens standing as the centre of

    the philosophical world.

    It

    was

    during Athenion s brief reign as tyrant that

    Athens suffered a crippling siege by Sulla s army, at the end of which the

    city was

    sacked. It is unclear how much physical damage was done during the

    siege to the traditional public meeting places of the schools (certainly both

    the Academy and the Lyceum, being outside the city walls, had been plun-

    dered for timber by Sulla).

    10

    It is possible that, even for a school like the

    Garden with its own private premises, the war made

    it

    too difficult to

    recruit pupils, especially from abroad. No doubt, in addition, the philoso-

    phers high political profile in these years made Athens too dangerous a place

    for some of them. But, whatever the precise reasons

    may

    have been, around

    the time of Sulla s capture of the city in 86 many philosophers left, and the

    Athenian Academy and Peripatos seem to have lost all institutional impor-

    tance. Philo and Antiochus, who fought for Plato s mantle, conducted their

    battle from Rome and Alexandria respectively, and it

    was

    above all in

    Alexandria that new philosophical departuresá occurred in the following dec-

    ades.

    It was

    largely there, for example, that the emerging generation of

    doctrinal Platonists now taught - such

    as Antiochus associates Ariston and

    Dion, and, soon after, the radical Platonist Eudorus. And

    it

    was there, at

    this time, that the influential revival of Pyrrhonist scepticism was centred,

    under the aegis of Aenesidemus,

    as

    well

    as

    the emergence of the more

    mysterious and probably short-lived Eclectic school, founded by Potamon.

    This eclipse of Athens did not extinguish philosophy there altogether. Ci-

    cero,

    11

    describing a nostalgic return to the Athenian schools in

    79

    BC,

    may

    concentrate on the memory of past glories, but he makes it clear that lectures

    by Antiochus can still be heard in the Ptolemaeum, and other lectures

    Çabout CarneadesÈ, apparently in the Academy, while his friend Atticus

    remarks that he spends much of his time with the Epicurean scholarch

    Phaedrus. Antiochus, although it is uncertain whether he ever became head

    CRONACHE ERCOLANESI

    34

    i

    i

    j

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    6/12

    of the Academy, did leave a school in Athens which was continued after his

    death by his brother Aristus and Aristus own successor Theomnestus. But

    there is no recorded trace of

    it

    after the 40s BC.

    As

    for the Epicurean

    Garden, it continued under the successive headships of Zeno of Sidon,

    Phaedrus, Patro and perhaps others, at least down to the time of Augustus;

    but

    we

    have seen, in the Rhodian episode, that its dominant status had

    already been lost by the time of Zeno s death in the 70s.

    f

    the philosophical centre of gravity had shifted away from Athens, one

    conjectural but extremely likely explanation is the dispersal of the school

    libraries. Warring Roman generals in the Greek east were well known to be

    on the look-out for libraries to seize, and Sulla proved no exception, bringing

    back to Rome from Athens, according to the story, some long-lost copies of

    Aristotle s school treatises. Just as the Athenian Peripatos had gone into

    decline after Theophrastus, on his death

    ca.287

    had bequeathed his books

    to Neleus of Scepsis, who promptly removed them from Athens, it is an

    attractive hypothesis that disruption of school libraries in the early 80s BC

    was a leading cause of Athens decline

    as

    a philosophical centre. It seems

    extremely probable that Philo of Larissa - still scholarch at the time -

    likewise brought all or most of the Academy s book collection with him into

    exile at Rome, rather than leave them to be added to Sulla s booty, and that

    the decline of the Athenian Academy from that date owes much to this

    depletion. What better explanation of the fact that Alexandria, with its

    magnificent library, was now to outshine it for many years?

    It is surely in this context that

    we

    should think of the library of Philodemus.

    Of

    course, many of the copies found in it

    may

    have been produced only after

    his move from Athens to Italy, but there can be little doubt that he brought

    with him, at the very least, that splendid antiquarian collection of books

    from Epicurus On nature of which many rolls have beeri identified. Given

    their great

    age

    there

    is

    every reason to assume that they were precious

    possessions acquired in the Garden itself during Philodemus time there.

    Certainly it was not merely a case of bringing essential reading matter with

    him on his journey to Italy: even in its present ravaged state, the collection

    includes multiple copies of a number of particularly valued books from

    Epicurus

    On nature.

    It is only reasonable to assume that the full collection

    included a great many more collector s items of this kind, precious relics of

    the school s Athenian history. One such is PHerc 176, a scroll whose hand

    dates

    it

    many years before Philodemus emigration.

    12

    Its author eulogises the

    kindly character of the early Epicurean Polyaenus, and its value to Philode-

    mus and his pupils is suggested by Diogenes Laertius report {X 24) that

    Polyaenus

    was

    Çdecent and companionable,

    as

    the circle of Philodemus sayÈ.

    Although

    we

    do not know at what date Philodemus left Athens for Italy, where

    he would enjoy Piso s patronage, the conjecture that it was during the Mithri-

    datic war, that is during or close to the crisis of 88-86, has a very strong claim on

    plausibility. This is the obvious date for the wholesale evacuation of book collec-

    tions from Athens to have occurred, in anticipation of Sulla s depredations.

    I turn now to iny second topic: to consider the impact of the philosophical

    dispersal on the way in which philosophers viewed themselves and their

    35

    DAVID SEDLEY

    12

    For the early dating of this and various

    other Herculaneum papyri, see G.

    CAvALLo

    Libri scritture scribi a Ercolano

    I Suppl.

    ÇCEreÈ 13/1983. The parts of

    PHerc

    176

    relative to Polyaenus are edited by A. TEPE-

    DINO GUERRA

    Polieno Frammenti (Naples

    1991).

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    7/12

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    8/12

    It is

    not always appreciated what an extraordinary fact

    it is

    that Diogenes

    Laertius, although writing around 300 AD, supplies us with a series of

    histories of philosophical successions nearly all of which end not later than

    the early to mid

    1st

    century BC. Take the Stoics. There were undoubtedly

    major Stoic thinkers

    of

    the imperial era. The often innovative philosophical

    work of such figures

    as

    Cornutus and Epictetus

    was

    well known

    not

    only in

    á their own day

    but

    also among later Platonist writers, including Simplicius.

    Yet it goes altogether unacknowledged by Diogenes Laertius.

    It

    is true that

    our book VII of Diogenes lacks its ending, and that the fuller index of

    contents found in two of the MSS takes the Stoic lives down through other

    names,

    as

    far as Cornutus. For

    my

    part, however, although I acknowledge

    that it has become controversial, I share the doubts thatáothers have ex-

    pressed

    as

    to the likelihood that the book, already the longest in the work,

    should have contained

    all

    these additional lives, especially as the same index

    fails to match accurately even the part of the book that

    we

    do possess.

    14

    But

    for present purposes, rather than rely on so contentious a hypothesis, I shall

    restrict myself to the following point. The very detailed Stoic doxography

    that the book includes in full constantly cites individual Stoics as authorities

    I do not mean

    as

    mere sources) for doctrines. These individual Stoics in-

    clude every major figure of the school from Zeno to Posidonius, and many

    minor ones, but not a single Stoic whose

    floruit

    was later

    than

    the mid

    1st

    century BC.

    In

    other words, the Stoic authorities taken seriously end with

    the last Stoic generation active in Athens in the early

    1st

    century BC,

    or

    at

    the very latest their immediate aftermath.

    15

    Nor is this silence - if such it is - a mere idiosyncrasy of Diogenes , for

    those illustrious later Stoics are equally unacknowledged by the mainstream

    doxographical tradition,

    as

    a glance at the index to Diels Doxographi Graeci

    will confirm. Here too we have compilers who, like Diogenes Laertius,

    regularly trace philosophical history only down to the early or mid

    1st

    cen-

    tury BC. The same pattern is broadly repeated outside the doxographical

    literature, for example in philosophical authors like Seneca, Plutarch, Dio-

    genes of Oenoanda and Sextus Empiricus.

    How can

    that

    be? It is not enough to postulate

    that all

    these writers were

    reliant

    on

    sources from the 1st century BC, since that, although perhaps

    broadly true, leaves unanswered the question why no effort should have

    been made to update or replace those sources. I see every reason to suppose

    that their practice is another manifestation of the attitude I have already

    described: with the demise of Athens

    as

    philosophical centre, the actual

    history

    of

    philosophy reaches its

    de facto

    end, and

    is

    replaced by the scholarly

    task of recording and understanding it.

    As

    Seneca wrote in a slightly differ-

    ent context,

    quae philosophia fuit, facta

    philologia est Ep. 108.23). The new

    mood might be compared, in some respects, to the slightly later advent of

    patristic scholarship, whose formal aim was to interpret rather than add to

    the sacred texts, even if in reality, at least from our perspective, it also

    became a major part of a continuous theological history that it purported

    merely to interpret . In the case of philosophy, the Athenian golden age could

    not simply be transported abroad and continued in other locations. The

    small philosophical circles which sprang up all around the Roman empire

    3 7

    DAVID SEDLEY

    14

    The correctness of the Çindex locupletiorÈ

    has, however, been defended by

    J

    MAN-

    SFELD,

    Diogenes Laertius on Stoic Philosophy,

    ÇElenchosÈ 7 (1986), pp. 310-312, and T.

    DoRANDI Considerazioni sull index locupletior

    di Diogene Laerzio, ÇPrometheusÈ 18 (1992),

    pp. 121-126.

    1

    5

    Athenodorus

    (DL

    VII 68 and

    121),

    if he is

    to be identified with Athenodorus Cordy-

    lion, is datable to the early part of the 1

    century BC

    cf. S.

    FoLLET

    Atbenodore de

    Tarse

    dit

    Cordylion R 18, in

    R.

    GouLET

    ed., Dictionnaire des philosophes antiques I,

    Paris 1989, p. 658 s.). Probably the latest

    Stoic cited by Diogenes as an authority is

    Antipater of Tyre, who, like Posidonius, died

    in the mid 1 century BC (Cic.,

    Off

    II 86);

    the fact

    (ibid.)

    that he appears to have re-

    tained Athens as his primary base may help

    explain his inclusion as an authoritative

    Stoic.

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    9/12

    16

    E.g.

    D.L. X 9.

    17

    D.L. X

    25 s.

    18

    D.L. X 3, 24.

    19

    Cf.

    M. GIGANTE Biografia e dossografia

    in

    Diogene

    Laerzio, ÇElenchosÈ 7 (1986),

    p.

    27,

    and

    La bibliotheque

    de

    Philodeme et l Epicuri

    sme

    romain (Paris 1987), p. 38.

    20

    R. PHILIPPSON Orion

    2, in RE XVIII.l,

    1 82

    s.

    were too far, in time, place and philosophical culture, from the classical

    Athenian schools to feel that they could participate in the life of these latter

    other than vicariously, through the study of their written legacy.

    Remarkably, even the Epicurean school

    is

    treated this way. Unlike the Stoa,

    Academy and Peripatos, we have good reason to accept,

    as

    I have said, that

    the Garden continued to exist

    as

    an Athenian institution for generations.

    16

    Yet Diogenes Laertius final book, devoted to the Garden, traces its succes-

    sion of distinguished Epicureans

    17

    only down to Zeno of Sidon, Demetrius

    of Laconia, and two others (Diogenes of Tarsus and Orion) who cannot be

    securely dated but are likely to be minor associates of these two. Philode-

    mus own generation is in effect missing, and there is not a word about later

    generations. One of the possible explanations is the hypothesis that Philo-

    demus himself is, directly or indirectly, the source. Diogenes has already by

    this point cited Philodemus and his circle twice as sources for Epicurean

    history in book X,

    18

    and since his first citation is explicitly from the tenth

    book of Philodemus Syntaxis, there is a serious possibility that - as Mar-

    cello Gigante proposed - it is to the model set by Philodemus that Diogenes .

    owes the ten-book structure of his own work, the decision to save Epicur-

    eanism for the final book, and even the strongly pro-Epicurean tone of that

    final book.

    19

    A possible further pointer is the curious ending to Diogenes list of Epicur-

    eans, Çand others whom the genuine Epicureans call sophistsÈ

    X

    26).

    Although it has proved hard to find this actual terminology of ÇgenuineÈ

    and ÇsophisticÈ Epicureans in Philodemus surviving writings, it does seem

    likely that either Philodemus or one of his close contemporaries is Diogenes

    source here.

    20

    We certainly know, from Philodemus writings, of fellow-

    Epicureans whom he denounced as untrue to the teachings of the school

    founders. And Diogenes way of putting it - Çothers whom the genuine

    Epicureans call sophistsÈ - sounds

    as

    if

    it

    must come from an Epicurean

    engaged in a factional rivalry within the school. No doubt one of the Çsoph-

    istsÈ,

    if

    he had instead been the source, would have reversed the claim and

    announced his own faction to be the ÇgenuineÈ one.

    The apparent fact that the list of names ends around the time of Philodemus

    suggests that this same Epicurean source was close in date to Philodemus. I f

    it

    is

    Philodemus himself, that hypothesis has the advantage of explaining why

    his own name

    is missing from the list. But, assuming that to be so, what is

    most significant is the absence from the list of Phaedrus or Patro, each of

    whom had almost certainly attained the headship of the Athenian school by

    the time Philodemus wrote his

    Syntaxis.

    Even for Philodemus himself, it

    would follow, the history of Epicurean philosophy

    as

    distinct from the pro-

    cess of its interpretation and dissemination} has come to an end decades

    earlier. If alternatively, we discount Philodemus as source,

    it

    remains equally

    significant that from Diogenes Laertius own perspective, regardless of his

    sources, the Epicurean school s history ends in the early 1st century BC.

    In Diogenes Laertius, the one unmistakable exception to the pattern I have

    described is Pyrrhonist scepticism. Although Sextus Empiricus, writing in

    the 2nd century AD, is yet another writer who conforms to the pattern,

    rarely if ever allowing philosophers later than the mid 1st century BC to

    CRONACHE ERCOLANESI

    38

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    10/12

    enter the debates he constructs, Diogenes Laertius history of Pyrronism in

    book IX does, in a brief appendix, trace the supposed history of the school

    after Timon, all the way down to Sextusá Empiricus and his own pupil

    Saturninus - in other words, very nearly down to Diogenes own time.

    This appendix is

    so

    condensed, however, that it might be said barely to

    constitute an exception. For example, Aenesidemus is named only in pas-

    sing, despite the fact that we have excellent evidence that his work was both

    innovative- indeed, the basis of the neo-Pyrrhonist movement that was to

    last for at least two centuries - and influential on other writers.

    On

    the

    other hand, the actual spokesmen for Pyrrhonism who are cited

    in extenso

    in

    the book do include Aenesidemus and, even later than him, Agrippa.

    Clearly, then, this book does not regard the early to mid 1st century

    BC

    as

    any kind of terminus. The likely explanation lies in the fact that Pyrrhonism

    had never been an Athenian-based movement (even

    if

    individual Pyrronists,

    like Timon, spent some time at Athens), and indeed the scene of its revival

    in the hands of Aenesidemus was Alexandria. It may be for that reason that

    the decline of Athenian philosophy

    was

    not deemed to bear on Pyrrhonism

    as it did on the leading four schools.

    t seems to

    me

    that at least the default position, for both Diogenes Laertius

    and the doxographical tradition more broadly, is that philosophical history

    terminates around the time of the demise of the Athenian Stoa. The latest

    Stoics to be cited by Diogenes Laertius are Posidonius and some of his

    approximate contemporaries, while the latest Stoic to be cited by Arius

    Didymus is Mnesarchus.

    t

    is worth pausing to ask what the exact standing

    of these two was, calling

    on

    the help of Philodemus.

    In the final column of the Index Academicorum, Philodemus appears to be

    claiming to have completed his catalogue of all Zeno s Stoic heirs (oi lSV ouv

    rco

    Z[l J]vrovo

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    11/12

    24

    FERRARY, op. cit., pp. 457-464, DoRANDI

    op. cit., p. 25.

    25

    Athenaeus 186A.

    26

    This explanation is suggested by the ana-

    logous attitude of Antiochus, who, in order

    to present himself

    as

    heir to the early Acad-

    emy, placed especial emphasis on the legacy

    of Polemo, not

    as

    the greatest of the early

    Academics,

    but as

    (to

    all

    intents and pur-

    poses) the last scholarch before the school

    deserted Plato, and hence

    as

    its best summa-

    tive spokesman. The alternative interpreta-

    tion proposed by FERRARY (seen.

    2

    above)

    does not fit so comfortably with the implica-

    tion of Athenaeus that these groups are his

    own contemporaries.

    after. But there is no evidence that either, let alone both, acceded to the

    headship of the school.

    24

    Philodemus, in his penultimate column (78), refers

    to someone who attended the lectures of Dardanus and Mnesarchus ÇtooÈ,

    and this again strengthens the impression that, while active and influential

    in Athens, neither of them became scholarch. Their being, in Cicero s

    words, the leading Stoics

    t

    Athens

    must surely be linked to the further fact

    - hardly a coincidence - that both were in fact, as we know from Philo-

    demus, themselves Athenians. They therefore had personal motives for re-

    maining in Athens even when others were leaving, and their high standing in

    Athens must owe a great deal to the departure of their competitors.

    Further confirmation of this reading of Philodemus - that Panaetius

    was

    the last scholarch in the list - lies in the following consideration. Athe-

    naeus,

    25

    writing in the 2nd century AD, knows of rival Stoic clubs calling

    themselves ÇDiogenistsÈ, ÇAntipatristsÈ and ÇPanaetiastsÈ. If as my argu-

    ment implies, Diogenes, Antipater and Panaetius were

    the

    last three formal

    heads of the Athenian school, it is a tempting inference that the later split

    between these groups named after the three of them represented three

    competing views among imperial Stoics

    as

    to which authority represented

    the culmination of the Athenian Stoic tradition before its virtual collapse.

    26

    The fact that Athenaeus list does not include a fourth group - whether

    named after Posidonius or after some other successor to Panaetius, such as

    Mnesarchus or Dardanus - tends to confirm that Panaetius was the last

    formally recognised Stoic scholarch. If as remains almost beyond doubt,

    Posidonius too

    was

    taken seriously by many later Stoics, it will have been

    by the Panaetiasts, Posidonius being Panaetius leading pupil and therefore

    probably his acknowledged spokesman too.

    It

    seems, at all events, that the latest Stoics acceptable to the later tradition

    as the school s philosophical spokesmen were Posidonius and his approxi-

    mate contemporaries, including Mnesarchus, and that these were so re-

    garded not because they ever became scholarchs, but because they repre-

    sented the final generation of Stoics whose roots lay in the school s Athenian

    headquarters.

    Given Posidonius enormous philosophical importance, it

    is

    a curious fact

    that his name does not occur anywhere in the admittedly meagre fragments

    of Philodemus

    Index Stoicorum

    I do not for a moment think that we should

    infer that he

    was

    excluded from the book. But it seems equally

    dear

    that no

    continuous stretch - o f say, a column and more -

    was

    devoted to him.

    Rather, he was simply included somewhere in a list of Panaetius pupils,

    without preferential treatment. The fact that Posidonius became head of the

    Stoic school in Rhodes was apparently not enough to counterbalance the

    minor status that followed from his never succeeding to the scholarchate at

    Athens. Since Philodemus engaged in debate with contemporary Stoicism,

    he surely knew of the reputation and influence of Posidonius, who had

    indeed published a direct critique of Philodemus own teacher Zeno of Sidon

    on geometry. Given the likely dating of the Index Stoicorum to fifty years

    or

    more after the death of Panaetius, its cursory treatment of ll the post-

    Panaetian Stoics cannot be explained merely by chronology.

    I t

    therefore

    seems to me probable that Philodemus historiographical practice, which

    CRONACHE ERCOLANESI

    40

    i

    j

    l

    i

    l

    ;

     

  • 8/18/2019 Sedley- decentralisation

    12/12

    effectively treats Panaetius as the last major Stoic, already enshrines a ver-

    sion of the principle that I described earlier: the history of philosophy stops

    with the exodus of the philosophers from Athens. At the chronological

    margin, figures of the last Athenian generation who outlived Panaetius, such

    as Posidonius and Mnesarchus, may be either given or denied prominence by

    different writers; but the broad principle remains intact.

    Does Philodemus history of the Academy conform to this pattern? Cer-

    tainly the last life that it treats with any expansiveness at all is that of Philo

    cols.

    33-4), scholarch at the time of the exodus. After that Antiochus -

    who

    if

    he ever became head of the Academy did so only after the period of

    exile - appears to be allotted somewhere between five and ten lines for his

    own biography; whereafter the book concludes, in its final column and a

    half, with a brief and rapid catalogue of the school s members and associates

    from the next generation, apparently not dwelling on any individual for

    more than a single sentence. The impression is confirmed once again that

    the exodus of philosophers from Athens in 88-86

    BC

    marks the point at

    which the historian s interest in the school effectively reaches its limit.

    Philodemus perspective shows that the historical watershed which subse-

    quent generations recognised in the early to mid st century BC was not

    imposed for the first time by them, long after the event and for possibly

    suspect motives of their own. t started with those who, like Philodemus

    himself, had actually joined the diaspora. These people were, after all, better

    placed than anybody to appreciate the massive gulf that separated their

    former philosophical life in their school s Athenian headquarters from their

    new life, one of teaching their discipline and its history to a local clientele,

    while continuing to study the school s treasured scriptures. Philosophy, they

    knew well, would never be quite the same again.

    27

    41

    DAVID SEDLEY

    27

    My thanks

    to

    James

    Warren

    for comments

    on an earlier version.