27
medical ethics workbook Case studies commentaries and activities Michael Parker Donna Dickenson THE CAMBRIDGE

Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

medical ethicsworkbook

Case studies

commentaries

and activities

Michael Parker

Donna Dickenson

THE CAMBRIDGE

Page 2: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom

The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, UK

40West 20th Street, NewYork, NY 10011-4211, USA

477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia

Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain

Dock House, TheWaterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa

http://www.cambridge.org

© Cambridge University Press 2001

This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception

and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,

no reproduction of any part may take place without

the written permission of Cambridge University Press.

First published 2001

Reprinted 2003

Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge

Typeface Utopia 9/12 pt System QuarkXPress™ [ ]

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

ISBN 0 521 78301 1 hardback

ISBN 0 521 78863 3 paperback

Every effort has been made in preparing this book to provide accurate and up-to-date information

which is in accord with accepted standards and practice at the time of publication. Nevertheless, the

authors, editors and publisher can make no warranties that the information contained herein is totally

free from error, not least because clinical standards are constantly changing through research and

regulation. The authors, editors and publisher therefore disclaim all liability for direct or consequential

damages resulting from the use of material contained in this book. Readers are strongly advised to pay

careful attention to information provided by the manufacturer of any drugs or equipment that they plan

to use.

Although case histories are drawn from actual cases, every effort has been made to disguise the

identities of the individuals involved.

Every effort has been made to reach copyright holders; the publishers would like to hear from anyone

whose rights they have unknowingly infringed.

Page 3: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Contents

List of cases page viiList of papers ixIntroduction xi

Part IEthical issues raised by devel-opments in modern medicine

1 End of life decision-making 3Section 1 Withdrawing treatment 3Section 2 Deciding not to resuscitate 7Section 3 Refusal of treatment and advance

directives 14Section 4 Euthanasia and physician-assisted

suicide 17Section 5 Ethics at the end of life: a case 22Section 6 The goals of medicine in palliative

care (revisited) 26Section 7 Decisions at the end of life involving

children 27

2 Genetic testing 36Section 1 Living with risk 36Section 2 Living with certainty 41Section 3 Genetics and reproductive choice 47Section 4 The use of genetic information 51

3 Reproduction 59Section 1 New reproductive technologies: benefit

or burden? 59Section 2 Fetal reduction and abortion 63Section 3 Compliance in pregnancy 67Section 4 A case study of high-risk pregnancy 74

4 Medical research 81Section 1 What counts as medical research? 82Section 2 Valid consent 93Section 3 Ethical implications of research

methods 108Section 4 The benefits and harms of medical

research 115

Part IIVulnerability, truth-telling,competence and confidentiality

5 Long-term care 125Section 1 Truth-telling 125Section 2 Autonomy, competence and

confidentiality 131Section 3 Ethics in relationships 144Section 4 The meaning and ethical

significance of old age 153

6 Mental health 160Section 1 Ethical conflicts in mental health 160Section 2 Consent to treatment and

compulsory hospitalization 166Section 3 Competence, autonomy and

advocacy 174Section 4 The mental health of children and

young people: presumed incompetent? 179Section 5 A different voice in psychiatric

ethics 184

7 Children and young people 192Section 1 The child in the family 192Section 2 Consent to treatment and the

child’s best interests 197

v

Page 4: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Section 3 Confidentiality and conflictingresponsibilities 206

Section 4 A question of competence? 209Section 5 The child in society 213Section 6 Making ‘the child’s voice’

meaningful 223

Part IIIBroader issues in medical ethics

8 Resource allocation 231Section 1 The problem of resource allocation 231Section 2 Deciding by medical criteria 235Section 3 Using social criteria to decide on

resource allocation 240Section 4 Health economics, markets and

healthcare rationing 249

Section 5 Philosophical models of resourceallocation 260

9 Thinking about ethics: autonomy andpatient choice 269Section 1 The importance of autonomy in

medical ethics 270Section 2 What is autonomy? 280Section 3 Autonomy: alternative models in

European law 283Section 4 Medical ethics: alternative models 289

Appendix 1: Study guide for teachers 312Appendix 2: The UK core curriculum 319

Glossary 323Bibliography 327Index 343

vi Contents

Page 5: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Cases

1 End of life decision-making 3The Case of Maria 4The Case of Mr R 8The Case of aWard of Court 12The Case of Mr C 15The Case of Helena 24The Case of JW 34

2 Genetic testing 36A Case of breast cancer genetics 36A Case of the right not to know 41Case –We want to test our children 42The Case of Alison 44A Case of sex selection 47

3 Reproduction 59A Case of high risk pregnancy 75

4 Medical research 81A Case of audit or research 82A Case of genetic research 93The Case of HIV drug trials in developing

countries 109An incomplete research ethics checklist 116A Case of research into the use of right heart

catheters 117

5 Long-term care 125The Case of Mr D 125The Case of the Forgetful Mourner 128The Case of Mrs B 131The Case of Mr A 132The Case of Lisa and Martin 144The Case of Emmi 154

6 Mental health 160The Case of Mr AB 160The Case of Mr L 170The Case of Mr C 175The Case ofW 179Vignette 1 183Vignette 2 183The Case of Miss A 185The Case of Miss B 186The Case of Mr C 187

7 Children and young people 192The Case of Peter 193The Case of Sean 195The Case of Emilia 197The Case ofW (revisited) 199The Case of JW (revisited) 200The Case of Pekka 203The Montjoie affair 206A Consent checklist 226The Case of Danny 226

8 Resource allocation 231The Case of Mr K 231The Case of baby Ryan 236The Case of ‘child B’ 237Case study: age cut-offs 242The Case of Margaret Davis 250

9 Thinking about ethics: autonomy andpatient choice 269The Case of Peter Noll 271The Case of Carl 280The Case of Dario Iacoponi 295The Case of Olle 310

vii

Page 6: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Papers

1 End of life decision-making 3Physician-assisted death, violation of the moral

integrity of medicine, and the slippery slopeRon Berghmans 5

Physician-assisted suicide in the case of mentalsuffering Ron Berghmans 18

The incompetent patient – sanctity of life,quality of life and vitalism John Keown 27

2 Genetic testing 36I am definitely having it done June Zatz 37Can children and young people consent to be

tested for adult-onset genetic disorders?Donna Dickenson 45

Sex selection: the case for Julian Savulescu 48The Icelandic database: do modern times need

modern sagas? Ruth Chadwick 51

3 Reproduction 59New reproductive technologies and practices:

benefits or liabilities for children?Christine Overall 60

The fewer the better? Ethical issues in multiplegestation Mary B.Mahowald 64

Judgements of non-compliance in pregnancyFrançoise Baylis and Susan Sherwin 68

Problems of paternalism and autonomy in a‘high-risk’ pregnancy Gillian M. Lockwood 75

4 Medical research 81Is this research? K.W.M. Fulford 83The 3Rs of medical research K.W.M. Fulford 90Autonomy and informed consent in the ethics

of the randomized controlled trial:philosophical perspectivesRichard Ashcroft 94

Ethical and legal issues concerning the involve-ment of vulnerable groups in medicalresearch Salla Lötjönen 103

Clinical research in developing countries:trials and tribulations Udo Schüklenk 110

A defence of HIV trials in the developingworld (based on NIH, CDC Statement) 112

The Nuremberg Code 115

5 Long-term care 125Truth and truth-telling GuyWiddershoven 127A commentary on the Case of Mr A Tony Hope 134Care for dependent elderly persons and

respect for autonomy Ruud ter Meulen 136Autonomy, feminism and psychiatric patients

Gwen Adshead 141Commentary on the Case of Lisa and Martin

Tony Hope 145Commentary on the Case of Lisa and Martin

GuyWiddershoven 148Commentary on the Case of Emmi

Chris Gastmans 154Commentary on the Case of Emmi

GuyWiddershoven 156

6 Mental health 160The psychiatric patient’s right to self-

determination MarittaVälimäki andHans Helenius 163

Self-determination in clinical practice: thepsychiatric patient’s point of viewMarittaVälimäki, Helena Leino-Kilpi andHans Helenius 165

Protection of the rights of the mentally ill in theNetherlands Ron Berghmans 166

TheWelie diagram SanderWelie 174

ix

All papers are reproduced with permission.

Page 7: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

ECT administration with children and adoles-cents: review of ethical considerationsSteve Baldwin andMelissa Oxlad 181

Drug treatment in child psychiatryCarlo Calzone 182

A different voice in psychiatric ethicsGwen Adshead 184

7 Children and young people 192Ethical issues in child psychiatry and child psy-

chotherapy: conflicts between the child,parents and practitioners John Pearce 201

Moral issues concerning children’s legal statusin Finland in relation to psychiatrictreatment Veikko Launis 204

Consent in children Donna Dickenson 209Ethical aspects of working with homeless

minors in London Michael Parker 214

8 Resource allocation 231Care for the elderly in an era of diminishing

resources Ruud ter Meulen 240The use of economic evaluation in healthcare

allocation Diane de Graeve andInes Adriaenssen 251

Markets, community and healthcare rationingDonna Dickenson 257

Age as a criterion for distributing scarcehealthcare resources Masja van den Burgand Ruud ter Meulen 262

9 Thinking about ethics: autonomyand patient choice 269Autonomy, feminism and vulnerable patients

Dolores Dooley 270The right to refuse treatment Christian Hick 272Conflicting ethical principles in intensive care

Juhani Pietarinen 276The concept of personal autonomy

Veikko Launis 280Three different models in European medical

law and ethics Donna Dickenson 284Out of the doll’s house Susan Mendus 290A virtue ethics approach Justin Oakley 296A deliberative approach to bioethics

Michael Parker 304

x List of papers

Page 8: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

Introduction

A medical man does not have to use all the techniquesof survival offered him by a constantly creative science.In many cases would it not be useless torture to imposevegetative resuscitation in the final stages of an incur-able sickness? The doctor’s duty here is rather to ease thesuffering instead of prolonging as long as possible, byany means whatsoever, a life no longer human (CardinalJean Villot, Vatican Secretary of State, 1970, quoted inMaguire 1975, p. 75).

Death is an intrinsic part of life. Increasingly,however, the techniques of modern medicine aremaking it possible for us to delay death and inmany cases to enable those who would have pre-viously died prematurely to recover and to live fulland healthy lives. However, such techniques alsoallow us to exert a greater degree of control overthe processes of dying even when full recovery isnot possible. This means that, in addition to thosewho recover, there are people who would previ-ously have died of their injuries, or condition,who can now be kept alive by medical interven-tions but who will never recover sufficiently to livean independent, or in some cases even a con-scious, life as a result. The use of these techniquesraises important ethical questions about the with-holding and withdrawing of such life-prolongingtreatment at the end of life. Indeed, the applica-tion of modern medicine at the end of life raises a

wide range of ethical questions, many of whichrequire a reconsideration of the purpose of medi-cine itself. When healing is no longer possible,what ought to be the goal of medicine and of thehealthcare professional? In this chapter we inves-tigate some of these questions by means of aseries of real cases. We look particularly at theethics of palliative medicine and attempt toanswer the question: to what extent are the ethicalimplications at the end of life different from, orthe same as, the ethics of medicine moregenerally?

Section 1: Withdrawingtreatment

We begin this chapter on ‘Decisions at the end oflife’ with a case from Greece. We decided to usethis case as the starting point both because itraises important ethical questions in itself andalso because it brings to the fore questions abouthow we ought to define the goals of medicine atthe end of life. Are there important morallysignificant differences between palliative medi-cine and medicine at other periods of life? If so,what are their implications for the practice, andindeed the goals, of medicine?

3

1

End of life decision-making

Section 1: Withdrawing treatment Section 2: Deciding not to resuscitate Section 3: Refusal of treatment andadvance directives Section 4: Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide Section 5: Ethics at the end of life: acase Section 6: The goals of medicine in palliative care (revisited) Section 7: Decisions at the end of lifeinvolving children

Page 9: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

THE CASE OF MARIA

Maria was an 82-year-old woman who lived inAthens. She had been seriously incapacitated byarthritis for over 2 years, and was also virtuallyblind following recent unsuccessful cataract andglaucoma treatment. As is very common inGreece, Maria was being cared for by her family inthe family home. Although Maria’s family foundthis quite difficult, they were coping reasonablywell.

However, Maria’s condition deteriorated drasti-cally when she suffered a severe cerebral vascularaccident (or stroke) and was admitted into hospi-tal. The result of the stroke was that Maria was leftin what her physicians called a ‘semi-coma’. Thedoctors at the hospital immediately began toprovide Maria with artificial nutrition and hydra-tion by means of a naso-gastric tube, but they toldthe family that they felt that no other treatmentwas appropriate as Maria was very unlikely torecover.

Maria’s family visited her regularly at the hospi-tal, but they found these visits very upsetting.Maria found it extremely difficult to speak andwas clearly very distressed. Whilst recognizing theseverity of Maria’s condition, her relatives, whocared for her a great deal, and the staff at the hos-pital were careful not to discuss this in her pres-ence. Despite this, it was clear from the start thatMaria herself found her situation intolerable and,during the first 6 weeks of her hospitalization,repeatedly expressed her wish to be allowed todie. She did this through the use of signs andhard-fought words, even though this was itselfextremely difficult and distressing for her. As shebecame increasingly frustrated, Maria also madeseveral repeated attempts to remove her feedingtube.

Clearly, this was also very upsetting for Maria’schildren, who were spending quite a lot of timewith her at this stage. They knew that their motherhad a lifelong aversion to hospitals and medicine,and they felt also a duty to respect her clearlyexpressed wish to die. After having discussed this

among themselves, Maria’s children togetherdecided to approach her physician about the pos-sibility of withdrawing treatment and allowing herto die, as she wished.

At their meeting with the physician, however,he made it very clear to the family in no uncertainterms that he would not consider acceding tosuch a request. He said that he felt that this wouldgo against his responsibilities as a doctor to hispatient. He also argued that Maria’s requests to beallowed to die should not be taken at face value asMaria had a recent history of mild depression.Maria’s family were unhappy with this decisionand with the doctor’s reasoning, but felt that theyhad no choice other than to accept it.

After a further week, however, Maria’s conditionhad deteriorated to such an extent that she wasnow in a full and irreversible coma and, afterfurther discussion with the family, the physicianagreed to withdraw nutrition but continued torefuse absolutely to withdraw the supply ofhydration.

Maria survived for another 2 weeks without res-piratory or other complications, but then diedrather suddenly when she suffered a secondstroke.

After the death of his mother, Maria’s son com-plained bitterly to the physician about the wayhis mother had been dealt with. He argued that,had the physician agreed with the family’srequest for the withdrawal of all kinds of treat-ment when this was originally requested, hismother would have died sooner and would havesuffered a great deal less than she did. He arguedthat, when it is clear that a patient is going to die,the doctor’s duty is to alleviate their suffering,and that this means that it can sometimes bewrong to keep a patient alive for as long as pos-sible and at all costs.

4 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY:Maria’s son felt that the doctor in this

case was being paternalistic and ignoring the wishes

of both Maria and her family.This raises the question

of who should decide in this kind of case. Stop here

Page 10: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

If one comes to the conclusion that the patienthas the moral right to be allowed to die, it istempting to jump from here to the claim that it isthe doctor’s duty to allow the patient to die, butclearly this need not be the case (we will bereturning to this point in Sections 2 and 4 of thechapter). The doctor in the case of Maria contin-ued to argue that, in his opinion, hydration wasnot simply another ‘form of treatment’ and was infact the most fundamental form of care that he asa physician felt it his duty to provide to anypatient. He argued that, whilst he was not infavour of prolonging unnecessarily a dyingpatient’s life, he felt that allowing a patient to diefrom lack of hydration was not what he consid-ered to be a dignified and peaceful death andwould, in fact, contravene his duty of care as adoctor. Moreover, he argued, to do so would havebeen against any medical and religious traditionof his country, Greece, and against his personalbeliefs.

The dispute between the doctor and Maria’sfamily appears to come down to one about whatthe goals of medicine ought to be in cases like thatof Maria. The family argued that, in situationswhere healing is no longer possible the centralgoal of medicine ought to be the alleviation ofsuffering. They ask, what was the aim of preserv-ing Maria’s life, when in the event she had anotherstroke and died? Did she suffer more than shewould have done were she simply allowed to dieafter the first stroke? The doctor’s view, on theother hand, appears to be that both the with-

drawal of hydration and allowing a patient to dieconstitute violations of the deepest kind of thegoals of medicine and of his duty of care to hispatient.

After you have done this, we would like you to goon to read the following extract from a papercalled ‘Physician-assisted death, the moral integ-rity of medicine, and the slippery slope’, by Dr RonBerghmans from the Netherlands. The reason weintroduce the paper at this point is because itraises and attempts to address this question ofwhether the goals of medicine in the broadestsense are in tension with, and perhaps evenconflict with, what we would consider ethicaltreatment or care at the end of life. Are the ethicaland moral dimensions different when questionsof life and death are at issue in this setting? Whilstyou are reading Berghmans’s paper we would likeyou to bear these questions in mind as they willform an important thread throughout the chapter.

Physician-assisted death, violation ofthe moral integrity of medicine, andthe slippery slope

Dr Ron Berghmans

Those who take the view that physician-assisteddeath involves a violation of the moral integrity ofmedicine argue that doctors must never be a party

Withdrawing treatment 5

for a moment and write down all the reasons you can

think of both for and against withdrawing treatment

when it was first requested by the family.

ACTIVITY: To what extent do you agree with the

doctor? What counts as treatment? Does hydration? Is

the withdrawal of hydration a violation of the doctor’s

fundamental duty of care for the patient?

ACTIVITY: Stop here for a moment and consider

what you think of as the goals of medicine.Make a list

of activities and attitudes which you consider to be

part of the goals of medicine in general as you see

them (i.e. not simply at the end of life) and another of

those which you would consider to constitute an

absolute violation of these goals.Then spend some

time reflecting on your list and ask yourself which of

these is no longer appropriate at the end of life, in

palliative medicine, if any. In this context which of the

list would you remove and what new activities and

attitudes would you add?

Page 11: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

to intentional killing, because that would goagainst the very essence of the medical profession(Singer & Siegler, 1990; Pellegrino, 1992;Momeyer, 1995). The essence of medicine fromthis perspective is considered to be healing andthe protection of life. This view is opposed to thepossibility of physician-assisted death in allcircumstances. Those who defend this view referto categorical claims such as the inalienability ofthe right to life, the sanctity of life, the absoluteprohibition against killing other human beings,and to healing as the single and ultimate goal ofmedicine. I want to focus on this last claim.

On this view, the essence of medicine is to befound in the telos of benefiting the sick by theaction of healing. It is worth asking, however, justwhat is the status of this claim. It should be recog-nised that the practice of medicine and the ends itserves are of human invention, and not ‘naturallygiven’ activities deriving from the structure ofnatural order. The practice of medicine is shapedby human beings in order to serve human pur-poses. It involves human choice with regard tovalue systems, and choosing such a value systemrequires moral argument and justification, not anappeal to the ‘nature of things’. Whatever the goalsof medicine are, or should be, is thus a matterwhich is open to rational debate, and cannot bedecided without reference to value considerations.

But even if, for the sake of argument, we agreethat the telos of medicine is healing – and not, forinstance, the relief of human suffering or the pro-motion of the benefit of patients – then we stillare left with the question of exactly what moralforce such an end or goal of medicine has. If welook at the actual practice of medicine, it is clearthat healing is more an ideal than an uncondi-tional goal of medical endeavour. Take forinstance the case of refusal of treatment by thepatient. A well-considered refusal of treatmentought to be respected, even if the physician takesthe view that treatment would be beneficial to thepatient. The reasons for respecting competentrefusals of treatment are twofold. The first reasonis that non-consensual intervention where aperson has decision-making capacity invades the

integrity of the person involved. The second is thatcompetent persons ought to be considered thebest judges of their own interests. Only the com-petent person himself can assess the benefits,burdens and harms of treatment in view of his orher wishes, goals, and values. So, if a personrefuses treatment because he or she does notvalue treatment in his or her personal life, thensuch a refusal ought to be respected, even if thismight result in an earlier death. Thus, as thisexample shows, healing as an ideal in medicalpractice implies that other goals and values canand do operate as constraints upon medicalactions serving this ideal.

More directly related to the issue of physician-assisted death is the consideration that the idealof healing can become illusory, for instance incases of severe and unbearable suffering in whichno prospect of alleviation exists. The goal of reliev-ing the suffering of the patient then becomes theprimary goal of the physician, rather than healing.

Part of the moral integrity argument is the claimthat, if physicians assist in suicide or euthanasia,then the public will begin to distrust the medicalprofession, and as a result the profession itself willsuffer irreparable harm (Pellegrino, 1992;Thomasma, 1996). Against this objection it can beargued that, if physician-assisted death is categori-cally rejected, the result may also be a loss of trustin the medical profession. The public may experi-ence this as a lack of compassion and personalengagement on the part of physicians in thosecases where no adequate means of relieving thesuffering of the patient are available and thepatient wants some control over how to die, but isleft alone by the doctor.

My conclusion is that, in principle as well as inpractice, euthanasia and physician-assisted suicidedo not necessarily go against the goal or goals ofmedicine, or the moral integrity of the medicalprofession. The Hippocratic vow of ‘helping thesick’ and of exercising medical skills for the benefitof patients does not prohibit the co-operation ofphysicians with requests for euthanasia andassisted suicide, so long as they are convinced thatthis is what is in a patient’s best interests and to

6 End of life decision-making

Page 12: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

the degree that the physician is committed torespecting a patient’s own values.

The involvement of doctors in the dying ofpatients is inescapable. In many cases, a decisionof a doctor leads to a hastening of death, althoughthat decision may not always be considered thedirect cause of the death of the patient (i.e. thedecision to respect the treatment refusal of apatient). In euthanasia and assisted suicide, thecausal role of the actions of the doctor is moreclear-cut, and the practice of physician-assisteddeath raises a number of issues regarding theproper role of the physician and the self-under-standing of the medical profession. Although theprimary task of the physician is to preserve the lifeof the patient, preservation of life is not an abso-lute goal. This would demand an unconditionalobligation to preserve life by all possible meansand under all circumstances. If the relief ofsuffering is also a proper goal of medicine, then inparticular circumstances a weighing or balancingof the goal to preserve life and the goal of reliev-ing suffering becomes inescapable.

Euthanasia and assisted suicide do not neces-sarily violate the moral integrity of medicine.

Two of those which Berghmans mentions are,firstly, the claim that if the public sees the medicalprofession engaged in ‘letting die’ it may under-mine the way in which the medical profession isperceived, and, secondly, that allowing the with-drawal of treatment under certain circumstanceswill lead to a slippery slope in which it is allowedin more and more cases which were not envisagedas being appropriate at the beginning. In hisarticle Ron Berghmans rejects each of these criti-cisms, but we will be coming back to explore themin more detail later on in the chapter.

In this first section of the chapter we haveraised the question of the goals or ‘telos’ of medi-

cine at the end of life. Both Berghmans andMaria’s son have proposed the hypothesis that thegoals of palliative care ought to be the alleviationof suffering, even if this sometimes goes againstour sense that, in general, medicine ought toconcern itself with healing. In the rest of thischapter we shall be going on to explore the ethicalimplications of this claim in a variety of differentways. In Section 2 we shall be going on to considerthe ethical implications of a decision not to resus-citate a patient.

Section 2: Deciding not toresuscitate

In the Greek case study examined in Section 1, thepatient was semi-comatose, although sheappeared to express her wish to have the feedingtubes withdrawn by trying to pull them out,making signs, and uttering a few hard-foughtwords. In this section we will begin with anothercase in which the patient lacks capacity toconsent to treatment. Here the issue is notwhether to continue intravenous feeding andhydration, but whether to resuscitate a severelydisabled patient if he suffers a cardiac arrest.Although the clinical picture is very different inthis case, however, the same theme arises.Because this patient, known as ‘Mr R’, appeared tobe in considerable suffering, this case gives rise tothe same question as did the Greek case: is it partof the telos of medicine to avoid the imposition ofunnecessary suffering by treating at all costs? Is itactually in the best interests of a suffering patientto impose treatment? Even in terms of the doctor’svalues and the telos of medicine, rather than therights of the patient, we will need to draw boun-daries that avoid a form of iatrogenic harm:

Deciding not to resuscitate 7

ACTIVITY: Stop for a moment and make a list of the

key points raised by this section.

ACTIVITY: Ron Berghmans’s argument for the claim

that the withdrawal of treatment in palliative care

does not violate the telos or goal of medicine is a pow-

erful one. But can you think of any counter-argu-

ments to this?

Page 13: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

imposing burdens without correspondingbenefits of treatment. In the case of patients whoare not competent to accept or refuse treatment,doctors’ main concern will be to avoid the imposi-tion of unnecessary suffering.

THE CASE OF MR R

(Re R [1996] 2 FLR 99)R was born with a serious malformation of thebrain and cerebral palsy. At 8 months of age hedeveloped severe epilepsy. At the age of 23 he wasspastic, incontinent, and apparently deaf andblind (with possible vestigial response to a buzzerand to light). He was unable to walk, to sit upright,or to chew; food had to be syringed to the back ofhis mouth. His bowels had to be evacuated manu-ally because his limited diet resulted in seriousconstipation. He suffered from thrush and hadulcers ‘all the way through his guts’, according totestimony. When cuddled he did indicate pleas-ure, and he also appeared to respond to pain bygrimacing. Although he was not comatose, nor ina persistent vegetative state, his awareness on ascale of 1 to 10 was rated somewhere between 1and 2 in an assessment by Dr Keith Andrews ofthe Royal Hospital for Neurodisability at Putney,London, who said:

It is my opinion that he has very little, if any, real cogni-tive awareness at a level where he can interpret what isgoing on in his environment. He reacts at the most basiclevel by responding to comfort, warmth and a safe envi-ronment by being relaxed and producing the occasionalsmile. He responds to discomfort, pain and threateningsituations by becoming distressed and crying. These arevery basic level responses and do not imply any thoughtprocesses.

Until he was 17 R lived at home, where he wastotally dependent on his devoted parents. He thenmoved to a residential home, but continued toreturn home at weekends. Now his condition wasbeginning to deteriorate: his weight had droppedto just over 30 kg, and he was extremely frail,suffering from recurrent chest infections, bleedingfrom ulceration of the oesophagus, and continuedepileptic fits. In 1995 he was admitted to hospital

on five occasions, each time for a life-threateningcrisis. After the last crisis Dr S, the consultantpsychiatrist for learning difficulties who wasresponsible for his care, wrote:

To hospitalize R if he had another life-threatening crisiswould, in my clinical judgement, be nothing more thanstriving officiously to keep him alive for no gain to him.In my opinion, this is tantamount to a failing against abasic duty of humanity. Indeed, at the last few admis-sions to hospital, I have had real concern as to whetherit was ethical to treat him actively. That said, I wouldnever withhold treatment against the wishes of hisparents. In summary, taking R’s best interests intoaccount and whilst taking into account the basicpremise of the sanctity of human life, it is in my judge-ment unquestionably in R’s best interests to allow natureto take its course next time he has a life-threateningcrisis and to allow him to die with some comfort anddignity. That would relieve him of physical, mental andemotional suffering.

8 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Go through the consultant’s opinion

again and write down the ethically charged terms or

concepts that are being used to construct an argu-

ment. After each term,write down the consultant’s

apparent interpretation of it. Do you agree with this

interpretation? If not, write down your own. For

example, ‘withhold treatment’ is crucial to the argu-

ment, and the consultant seems to be saying that

withholding treatment is ethically acceptable pro-

vided that R’s parents agree. Nothing is said about

actively ending R’s life; rather the emphasis is on ‘pas-

sively’ withholding treatment which could be under-

taken, but which it would actually be ethically wrong

to administer.We shall return later in this section to

arguments about the ethical validity of the distinction

between withholding care and actively initiating

death.The British Medical Association published

guidance on withholding and withdrawing life-

prolonging treatment in 1999 in which they asserted

that:

Although emotionally it may be easier to withholdtreatment than to withdraw that which has beenstarted, there are no legal, or necessary morally rele-vant, differences between the two actions (BMA, 1999).

Page 14: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

How did you get on with the list of ethicallycharged terms? In addition to withholding treat-ment, we identified these key underlying con-cepts/arguments:(a) Best interests of the patient(b) Sanctity of life(c) Relief of suffering(d) ‘Basic duty of humanity’(e) ‘Gain’ or benefit to the patient(f) Treating actively (as against the implied alter-

native of allowing nature to take its course)(g) Wishes of the parents(h) Death with dignity(i) Medical futility: the question of how to judge

when treatment is no longer effectiveQuite a full list for one paragraph. This exerciseillustrates how tightly packed with ethical con-cepts an apparently clinical judgement can be.

Now please continue reading the case of Mr R.

THE CASE OF MR R (cont.)

The immediate question now was whether toresuscitate R in the event of another acute admis-sion resulting in cardiac arrest. He was so frail thatit was feared CPR (cardio-pulmonary resuscita-tion) might crush his ribcage. In addition, therewas a risk of further brain damage from resuscita-tion. A subsidiary question was whether toadminister antibiotics if he developed pneumo-nia. After R’s fifth hospital admission, inSeptember 1995, the consultant. Dr S, discussedthe position with R’s parents. They agreed that Rwould not be subjected to CPR if he suffered acardiac arrest in future. Accordingly, Dr S signed aDNR (do not resuscitate) direction, signed by R’smother under the heading ‘next of kin’.

This decision was opposed by staff at the daycare centre which R had been attending; they feltthat he did, in fact, have some ‘quality of life’. In

addition they interpreted Dr S’s decision as a ‘notreatment’ policy, which Dr S denied: the onlytreatment which she was withdrawing, sheargued, was cardio-pulmonary resuscitation.Agreement could not be reached, and a memberof the day care centre staff applied for review ofthe decision by a court, on the basis of informa-tion provided by social workers involved in R’s daycare. The basis of the application was that theDNR (do not resuscitate) decision was irrationaland unlawful in permitting medical treatment tobe withheld on the basis of an assessment of thepatient’s quality of life. The hospital sought acourt judgement that despite R’s inability to give avalid refusal of treatment, it would be lawful andin his best interests to withhold cardio-pulmonaryresuscitation and the administration of antibio-tics. A proposed gastrostomy would be per-formed, however, underlining that there was noquestion of comprehensive refusal to treat R.Likewise, the hospital decided that it would venti-late R and provide artificial nutrition and hydra-tion if applicable, although initially it hadindicated it would not. The application made itclear that the hospital intended ‘to furnish suchtreatment and nursing care as may from time totime be appropriate to ensure that [R] suffers theleast distress and retains the greatest dignity untilsuch time as his life comes to an end’.

At the High Court hearing, where R was repre-sented by the Official Solicitor (who acts on behalfof incompetent patients), discussion centred onguidelines for resuscitation issued by the BritishMedical Association in 1993 (Revised, 1999) in ajoint statement with the Royal College of Nursing.Resuscitation, originally devised to be used in asmall minority of cases, is now overused, it hasbeen argued (Hilberman et al., 1997). Althoughthe technique can be very successful in the rightcontext, at least in some US states it has becomethe default response to cardiac arrest, requiredunless it is explicitly refused or clearly ‘futile’. Yetcardiac arrest is part of death. But was R dying?

The 1993 BMA/RCN guidelines, as used in the R

Deciding not to resuscitate 9

What do you think about this claim? Can you think of

any arguments in favour or against it?

See also the Government’s White Paper ‘Making

Decisions’, 1999.

Page 15: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

decision, did not actually say that resuscitationmust always be attempted unless the patient isclearly in a terminal condition. Instead, theysuggest three types of case in which it is appropri-ate to consider a DNR decision:(a) where the patient’s condition indicates that

effective cardio-pulmonary resuscitation(CPR) is unlikely to be successful

(b) where CPR is not in accord with the recordedsustained wishes of the patient who is men-tally competent

(c) where successful CPR is likely to be followedby a length and quality of life which would notbe acceptable to the patient.

Condition (a) is the most obviously clinical of thethree. It focuses solely on the medical facts of thematter. Certainly R is gravely ill, but he has comethrough five acute admissions in the past year, sothat it is difficult to say that he is definitelyunlikely to survive CPR. Condition (b) cannot bemet, because R is not mentally competent torecord a wish. Although the consultant says thatshe would never terminate his care against hisparents’ wishes, in English law the parents of anadult have no power to accept or refuse treatmenton his behalf (although at the time of writing, thiswas open to change after consultation on propo-sals for appointment of proxy decision-makers asput forward by the Law Commission (LawCommission, 1995: Lord Chancellor’sDepartment, 1997)). (In most other Europeanjurisdictions – for example, Greece – and in manyAmerican states, proxy decision-making on behalfof an incompetent adult is in fact possible.) TheBMA guidelines merely noted that the opinions ofrelatives ‘may be valuable’ – not determining.Finally, we have condition (c), focusing on unac-ceptable quality of life – but again, acceptable orunacceptable to the patient. It is very hard toknow whether R gets any enjoyment out of life: heseems to respond to being cuddled, and to reactto pain, but that is really all we can say. Again, the

BMA guidelines did note that: ‘If the patientcannot express a view, the opinion of others closeto the patient may be sought regarding thepatient’s best interests.’ But the guidelines do notsay that opinion has anything more than advisoryvalue as to what the patient would regard as rea-sonable quality of life. They also appear to envi-sion a different kind of situation – where apreviously competent patient, who (unlike R) hadexpressed definite views about good and badquality of life, is no longer able to enunciate his orher wishes, but where the family will rememberhis or her preferences. (We will return to theimportant issue of quality of life in Section 6.)

So, strictly speaking, it is possible to make acase for arguing that none of these conditionsapplies to R. But that was not the opinion of theCourt. Prompted by guidance from Keith Andrewsas an expert witness, the Court agreed that condi-tions (b) and (c) were not applicable – ruling outthe quality of life arguments both for and against.Only condition (a) was to be considered, that is,the likelihood rather than the desirability of suc-cessful CPR. Even in hospital settings only about13 per cent of patients receiving CPR survive todischarge, Dr Andrews testified; in a residentialhome such as the one R lived in, the chanceswould be virtually nil. Accordingly, the caseturned on the futility of treatment, rather than onquality of life. On the basis of medical futility, theCourt accepted the DNR order, but not a globalpolicy against other interventions by the consul-tant when, and if, a potentially life-threateninginfection arose.

There is quite widespread distrust of the conceptof medical futility (e.g. Gillon, 1997) as excessivelypaternalistic. Because it purports to be a purely‘scientific’ criterion, it allows the doctor to decide,rather than in consultation with the patient. It isnever possible to say that, in this particular case, a

10 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Which, if any, of these conditions might

apply to R? Note down the reasons for your answer.

ACTIVITY: Stop here for a moment and try to devise

a possible counter-argument to this view.What might

be the pitfalls of using medical futility to decide

whether or not to resuscitate?

Page 16: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

treatment will or will not be completely futile;rather, it is a question of what levels of probabilityare acceptable. That decision should rest with thepatient, it can be argued, and not with the doctoralone. Of course, in the case of R, no consultationwith the patient was possible, and Dr S’s decisionwas accepted by the parents. But we have alreadyseen that the parents’ opinion is only advisory inEnglish law. And it might be argued that preciselybecause Dr S couldn’t know whether R would havethought resuscitation futile, she should have erredin favour of administration of CPR, rather than aDNR order.

One argument in favour of using medical futil-ity as a criterion is that it is simply unavoidable.Unless we want to say that treatment shouldalways be provided to a competent patient whorequests it, or to an incompetent patient whateverthe circumstances, then someone has to draw theline somewhere. That person is most likely to bethe doctor (Brody, 1997).

Whichever you believe, the R case centres onwhat duties doctors have to avoid imposingsuffering, unless suffering has a point. It is whensuffering is pointless, in the face of unacceptableburdens for little benefit, that the decision not toresuscitate appears valid. The issue is who decideswhat is unacceptable, and on what basis.

Acts, omissions and the doctrine of doubleeffect

The R judgement emphasized that ‘there is noquestion of the Court being asked to approve acourse aimed at terminating life or acceleratingdeath. The Court is concerned with circumstancesin which steps should not be taken to prolonglife.’ The distinction here is between acts andomissions, a distinction originating in Catholicmoral theology and also found in other contexts.The wording in the Anglican creed, for example,asks God to pardon believers for two separatematters: that ‘we have done those things we oughtnot to have done’ (wrongful acts) and that wehave ‘left undone those things we ought to havedone’ (wrongful omissions). In the medical

context, this Catholic tradition would hold that adecision to withhold treatment ‘is not the equiva-lent of suicide; on the contrary, it should be con-sidered as an acceptance of the human condition,or a wish to avoid the application of a medicalprocedure disproportionate to the results that canbe expected’ (in the words of the Vatican’s 1980Declaration on Euthanasia).

It is often difficult to distinguish between actsand omissions in practice. For example, is turningoff a ventilator a positive act, or merely omittingto perform the treatment any longer? More radi-cally, however, some philosophers, those whoconcentrate on the consequences of actions, donot accept the acts/omissions distinction, noteven in principle. This is true of utilitarians suchas James Rachels (Rachels, 1986), who argues thatthere is no significant moral difference betweenkilling and letting die, and Jonathan Glover, whouses this example:

A man who will inherit a fortune when his father dies,and, with this is mind, omits to give him medicine nec-essary for keeping him alive, is very culpable. His culpa-bility is such that many people would want to say thatthis is not a mere omission, but a positive act of with-holding the medicine. Supporters of the acts and omis-sions doctrine who also take this view are faced with theproblem of explaining where they draw the line betweenacts and omissions. Is consciously failing to send moneyto [charity] also a positive act of withholding? (Glover1977, p. 96).

Supporters of the distinction might answerGlover’s challenge by saying that the point atwhich to draw the line is the doctor’s duty to care.It is because the son has a duty to care for thefather that failing to give the medicine is wrong.(It might also be wrong to fail to give it to anyonewho needed it, if we think we have a generalized‘Good Samaritan’ duty to others.) In the context ofa doctor’s duty to care, both acts and omissionsmay indeed be wrongful: treating without consentwould be a wrongful act, whilst failing to treatsomeone who had consented and who neededtreatment might be a wrongful omission.

This may explain why doctors are often reluc-tant to rely on the distinction between acts and

Deciding not to resuscitate 11

Page 17: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

omissions, why they feel a duty to treat at all costs– sometimes against relatives’ wishes. This sort ofscenario is illustrated by a 1995 Irish case, knownfor reasons of confidentiality only as ‘in the matterof a ward of court’.

THE CASE OF A WARD OF COURT

The case concerned a young woman who, at theage of 22, underwent a minor gynaecologicaldiagnostic procedure under general anaesthetic.During the procedure she suffered three cardiacarrests, resulting in serious anoxic brain damage.Doctors continued to maintain her in what theytermed ‘a near-persistent vegetative state’ for over20 years, feeding her first by nasogastric tube andthen by gastrostomy. (She continued to breathenormally; ventilation was not required, exceptbriefly after her cardiac arrests.) For many yearsshe was in a rehabilitation centre, and was thentransferred to a hospice, whose philosophy wouldnot allow withdrawal of feeding tubes.

After almost 23 years her family sought an orderthat all artificial hydration and nutrition shouldcease, and that the Court should give such direc-tions as to her care. Against public expectations,they succeeded in obtaining a Supreme Courtjudgement allowing treatment to be withdrawn.Non-treatment of any possible infections was alsogranted. With the Court’s authorization, the Wardwas brought home from the hospice, where vol-unteer nurses and doctors assisted in withdraw-ing the feeding tubes and caring for her until shedied a week later. (They did so in contravention ofguidelines from the Irish Medical Council andIrish Nursing Board, which refused, even after theSupreme Court judgement, to retreat from theirinsistence that ‘feeding is a universal requirementin the care of human beings, and whether or notthis feeding is done through tube mechanismsdoes not alter this moral position.’) (Irish MedicalCouncil Guidelines of 4 August 1995)

The prayer card for the Ward’s memorial massgave two dates of death: the first in 1972, the timeof the accident, and the second in 1995, when shewas finally allowed to die.

Although the Supreme Court judgement eventu-ally upheld the notion that the Ward’s best inter-ests did not require active treatment which hadlittle chance of success, the family were angeredby doctors’ refusal to listen to this argumentearlier – as Dolores Dooley of University CollegeCork makes plain.

Following a minor diagnostic procedure under anaes-thetic, Ms X was left severely brain-damaged. She would,in all probability, never recover cognitive functioning,never be able to move voluntarily, and never be able tocommunicate by choice. The family wanted life-supporttherapies to be ended when the prognosis became clear.

But they were baffled and angered by the marginaliza-tion they experienced as many decisions were takenunilaterally and without consultation. They tried to ask:why resuscitate her on numerous occasions when allbodily evidence indicated she was trying to die? Whyreinsert an abdominal feeding tube under anaestheticonly 6 months before her death, when their daughterhad been in a ‘near-persistent vegetative state’ for 22years? Why not provide the best of pain relief care (if sheknew pain) and allow her dying to proceed naturally?What were the healthcare goals for this patient, and whywere they not discussed with the family? What was theobjective of such aggressive life-support measures?What moral imperatives were guiding these decisions?

We would say that resuscitation is clearly an act,and a medical procedure. Insertion of an abdomi-nal feeding tube is likewise active medical treat-ment, according at least to the decision inAiredale NHS Trust v. Bland (1993). (In this, one ofthe first such cases in Europe, withdrawal offeeding tubes was authorized for a young man leftin a persistent vegetative state, although basicnursing care continued to be required.) Providingpain relief is a more difficult issue, even though itis an act rather than an omission.

Suppose that the issue in R had not been resus-citation, but the administration of pain relief insuch quantities as were likely to accelerate death –again, with the intention of avoiding unnecessarysuffering. The final words in the R judgement

12 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Which of the procedures in the previous

paragraph is an act, and which is an omission?

Page 18: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

stress this: ‘His parents, his doctors and thedevoted and selfless care workers will continue tospare no effort to make his life as bearable and ascomfortable as possible until a crisis occurs whichwill result in Nature taking its course and R beingrelieved of intolerable suffering.’ Could this carerightfully include pain relief? Clearly it could; thehospital stressed that it had never sought a ‘no-treatment’ order, and that it intended to make R’sdeath as comfortable and dignified as possible.But could it include pain relief at levels whichmight actually hasten R’s death? (Of course, it is amisconception to believe that pain relief alwaysnecessarily shortens life.) That seems a differentmatter from letting nature take its course: it is anactive step. So far, we have distinguished betweennot doing everything that could be done – pas-sively accepting the inevitability of death – andactively trying to bring it about. But this examplelies uncomfortably between the two. It begins tosound more like active euthanasia and less like‘letting die’.

According to the principle of ‘double effect’ it is some-times perfectly proper if one’s conduct unintentionallyhas the effect of shortening, or of not lengthening, life.For example, the doctor who, with the intention ofeasing pain, administers morphine to a terminally illcancer patient may foresee that this will shorten thepatient’s life. But the shortening of life is merely an unin-tended side-effect of the doctor’s intention to alleviatepain, and there is a very good reason (namely the allevi-ation of pain) for allowing that bad side-effect tohappen. He is not attacking the patient’s life but thepatient’s pain.

Similarly, a doctor may sometimes properly withholdor withdraw treatment even though the doctor foreseesthat the patient’s life will be shorter than it would bewith the treatment. [In this view] a doctor is under no

duty to administer (and patients are fully entitled torefuse) disproportionate treatments, that is, treatmentswhich would either offer no reasonable hope of benefitor would involve excessive burdens on the patient. Evenif the doctor foresees that the patient’s life will not be aslong without the treatment as it would have been with it,the patient’s earlier death is merely an unintended side-effect of the doctor’s intention to withhold or withdraw adisproportionate treatment.

Perhaps one candidate is the concept of an ‘unin-tended side-effect’. Must we take a doctor’s wordthat the side-effect was merely foreseen and notintended? Surely there is a risk of hypocrisy here?Against that charge, it can be argued – convinc-ingly, in our view – that if the doctor is not disap-pointed when the unintended side-effect fails tooccur, it really is unintended. That is, if thepatient’s pain is relieved, and the patient does notdie, the doctor genuinely abiding by the doctrineof double effect should be pleased rather than dis-appointed. He or she has truly intended the goodeffect and merely tolerated the possibility of thebad one.

Put in Keown’s terms, the unifying factorbetween the withdrawal of treatment and theadministration of possibly fatal pain relief isintention, rather than the action itself. In bothcases the intended effect (the relief of suffering) isgood. However, one might argue that is also theintention in active euthanasia. We will return tothat problem in Section 4, where we discuss a caseof actively assisting suicide. For now, we wouldlike you to undertake one final activity beforefinishing this section.

Deciding not to resuscitate 13

ACTIVITY: Another concept from Catholic moral

theology, the doctrine of double effect, describes this

situation. In the paragraphs which follow, John

Keown, a medical lawyer at Cambridge University,

outlines the doctrine. Read the account through,

writing down the various claims underlining the prin-

ciple (Keown, 1997).

ACTIVITY: What is the weakest spot in this argu-

ment?

ACTIVITY: Thinking back to the case of Mr R. in the

light of the arguments you have explored thus far, do

you think it would have been justifiable for Dr S to

administer pain relief to R in the knowledge that his

death might be accelerated? Jot down any conditions

that you would want to impose on her power to do so.

Page 19: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

In Catholic doctrine there are four conditionswhich must be fulfilled if a good action with a badside-effect is to be allowed:(a) The action, considered by itself and indepen-

dently of its effects, must not be morallywrong.

(b) The bad effect must not be the means of pro-ducing the good effect.

(c) The bad effect must be sincerely unintended,and merely tolerated.

(d) There must be a proportionate reason for per-forming the action in spite of its bad potentialconsequences (Veatch, 1989).

In the case of R it seems to us that all these condi-tions can be met. There is nothing morally wrongwith administering pain relief, in itself; indeed, itis morally good to relieve others’ suffering. Death,if defined as the bad effect, is not the means ofproducing the good effect of pain relief, as wouldbe the case if, say, Dr S administered a lethal doseof potassium chloride – whose only functionwould be to bring about R’s death. We havealready considered the third condition: if Dr S isnot disappointed in the event that R does not die,then she genuinely does not intend his death.Finally, there is clearly a proportionate reason forperforming the action, that is, the relief ofsuffering. All this is premised on Dr S’s own feel-ings about the ethical acceptability of such acourse.

Although the answer to this question might obvi-ously seem ‘yes’, you might also like to considerthe opposite point of view: that patients can beharmed if doctors exercise their rights of con-science. In an American case, Beverley Requena, acompetent woman of 55 who was on a ventilatorin a church-affiliated hospital, decided to refusetube feeding (Miles et al., 1989). This contradictedthe hospital’s ethical code, but hospital manage-ment offered to transfer her to another institution

which would honour her refusal. Ms Requenarefused the transfer; in all other respects she washappy with the care she was receiving in thechurch-affiliated hospital, and it was there thatshe wanted to die. The hospital brought a suit toforce Ms Requena to transfer, but failed in court.There the judge directed the hospital to recon-sider its beliefs in a more flexible manner. Thecase of Beverley Requena makes a good link to thenext section of this chapter, in that it concerns alegally competent patient.

In this section, as in Section 1, we have lookedat ethical issues in the care of patients who cannotexpress a preference in their own end-of-life deci-sions. In the next section we move on to the com-petent patient. How comprehensive is the duty torelieve suffering there?

Section 3: Refusal of treatment and advancedirectives

In the previous two sections we looked at thegoals of medicine in the care of dying patientswho are not competent to choose or refuse treat-ment. There, the clinician’s main concern was toavoid imposing unnecessary suffering, in the bestinterests of the patient. But what happens whendoctors also have to take into account the views ofpatients? Here and in Section 4 we move on tocases of competent patients – although in boththese cases the patient’s competence was border-line, for reasons of mental illness. In Section 3 weconsider the UK case of Mr C, a long-term mentalpatient who was allowed to refuse amputation ofa gangrenous leg; in Section 4, we look at theDutch case of Dr Chabot, who assisted the suicide

14 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Is it always up to the doctor’s individual

moral beliefs? Should doctors have the right to refuse

to carry out treatments that contradict their own

moral beliefs?

ACTIVITY: Make a list of the key points raised by

this section.

Page 20: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

of a clinically depressed but otherwise healthywoman.

Even if healing and/or the relief of suffering aretaken to be the unquestionable goals of medicine,that does not justify the doctor’s imposing his orher goals and values on those of the competentpatient. Treating patients without their informedconsent, even in the name of their best interests,is an unacceptable invasion of personal integrity,in this argument about what is ethically right andwrong – and that is also the legal position in mostEuropean jurisdictions. Even at the end of life, orat the risk of death, a competent adult patient hasan absolute right to refuse treatment, as RonBerghmans explains.

A well-considered refusal of treatment ought to berespected, even if the physician takes the view that treat-ment is beneficial to the patient. The reasons forrespecting competent refusals of treatment are twofold.The first reason is that non-consensual interventionwhere a person has decision-making capacity invadesthe integrity of the person involved. The second is thatcompetent persons ought to be considered the bestjudges of their own interests. Only the competentperson himself can assess the benefits, burdens andharms of treatment, in view of his or her wishes, goalsand values. So, if a person refuses treatment because heor she does not value treatment in his or her personallife, then such a refusal ought to be respected, even ifthis might result in an earlier death. Although healing isan ideal in medical practice, other goals and values canand do operate as constraints on medical actionsserving this ideal (Berghmans, 1997a).

But what does Berghmans mean by ‘a well-con-sidered refusal of treatment’? Might one arguethat refusing treatment which is medically advis-able is automatically ill-considered? That this kindof reasoning does occur in practice has beenextensively documented (e.g. Roth et al., 1977;Faulder, 1985; Culver and Gert, 1982) and, in thecase of young people under 18, it has actuallybeen upheld in law (Re R [1991]). The argumenthere is that refusal should carry a heavier ‘tariff’than consent to treatment, because it goes againstmedical opinion. But that is different from sayingthat a refusal can never be ‘well considered’, even

if it flies in the face of medical opinion. As anothercourt ruled in an earlier decision, ‘the patient isentitled to reject [medical] advice for reasonswhich are rational, or irrational, or for no reason’(Sidaway v. Bethlem RHG, 1985).

We will now look briefly at a case which illus-trates the criteria for competence. (This case isconsidered at greater length in the mental healthchapter.)

THE CASE OF MR C

Mr C, aged 68, had been detained in a securemental hospital for 30 years as a paranoid schizo-phrenic. His delusions included the belief that hisdoctors were torturers, whilst he himself was aworld-famous specialist in the treatment of dis-eased limbs. When his own foot became infected,he therefore hid his condition from medical per-sonnel until it had actually become gangrenous.His doctors believed that unless his foot wasamputated, he stood an 80 to 85 per cent chanceof dying.

Mr C, however, refused to consent to the ampu-tation, saying that he would rather die intact thansurvive with only one foot. He sought reassu-rances from the hospital that his foot would notbe amputated without his consent if he slippedinto a coma. The health authority in charge of thehospital refused to give an undertaking not toamputate his foot without his consent. Mr C thensought a High Court order to prevent amputationif he became unconscious.

As Mr C’s solicitor, Lucy Scott-Montcrieff,explained:

The issue at the heart of all of this was whether or notMr C had the capacity to refuse the treatment that wasbeing offered to him. Mental illness doesn’t of itselfmean that a person doesn’t have capacity; you couldhave capacity for some things and not other things. Wehad to establish whether Mr C could understand and

Refusal of treatment 15

ACTIVITY: Do you think Mr C was competent to

refuse consent to treatment? Jot down the principal

reasons why, or why not.

Page 21: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

retain the information about the advantages and disad-vantages of amputation and the advantages and disad-vantages of not having amputation. The surgeon who’dbeen treating Mr C gave evidence; what he said was thathe believed that Mr C did have capacity, because Mr C’sviews about capacity fitted in a very normal sort of waywith the views of other elderly people with vasculardisease who got gangrene more or less at the end of theirlives. They didn’t want to spend their last few yearseither coping with an amputation or possibly copingwith repeated amputation as the vascular system fails allround the body. So the order was made that the hospitaltrust shouldn’t amputate his foot without his permission(BBC, 1995).

In the event, Mr C survived, and his case madelegal history in the UK for two reasons which arevery important to the wider concerns of thischapter. Firstly, it established a clear set of criteriafor competence.(a) Capacity to comprehend and retain informa-

tion about the proposed treatment. Mr C wasfound to have this capacity, in part because itwas shown that, in other aspects of everydayprudence, such as budgeting, he was able totake ‘sensible’ decisions. Further, it was heldthat what mattered was the narrowly con-strued ability to comprehend and retain infor-mation about this particular decision, on afunctional basis, not capacity in some generalsense. Given the general presumption of com-petence in adults, the doctors had to establishthat Mr C did not possess this capacity; thecourt held that this had not been proved.

(b) Belief in the validity of the information (seealso Re MB, 1997). It might be thought ques-tionable whether Mr C really believed whatthe doctors told him; after all, he thought theywere torturers. Perhaps he also believed, in hisdelusions about his own medical ‘stardom’,that he knew better than the hospital physi-cians. Nevertheless, the court held that Mr Calso met this criterion.

(c) Ability to weigh up the information so as toarrive at a choice. Mr C had balanced the risksand benefits differently from the doctors, butthat did not invalidate his decision, particu-

larly because an expert witness had testifiedthat many other elderly people came to thesame conclusion.

Secondly, the C case concerned the validity ofadvance directives, sometimes called living wills:statements made while a patient is competent,concerning what forms of treatment he or shewould wish to refuse in the event of becomingincompetent, e.g. through coma or persistent veg-etative state (Law Commission, 1995; LordChancellor’s Department, 1997). (Because thegeneral purpose of advance directives is to specifytreatment which would not be considered accept-able, they are also sometimes known as ‘advancerefusals’.) They can be either written or oral, MrC’s was a witnessed verbal refusal. Advance direc-tives illustrate in practical form the distinctionintroduced in the previous section between actsand omissions. They rest on the legal and ethicaldistinction between acting to do everything whichcould be done to relieve suffering – regardless ofwhat the patient wants – and respecting thepatient’s right to request that certain forms oftreatment should be omitted.

In the UK, at the time of writing (early 2000), ithas been emphasized that ‘certain forms ofadvance statement already have full effect atcommon law’ (Lord Chancellor’s Department,1997, p. 23). The conditions are that an advancerefusal must be ‘clearly established’ and ‘appli-cable in the circumstances’. In that case the refusalis as binding as that of a competent, consciousadult. ‘An advance refusal made with capacitysimply survives any supervening incapacity.’ (LawCommission, 1995). However, because there wasno statutory provision at the time of writing –although a consultation document was laying thegrounds for such legislation – it was still necessaryto go to court in order to establish the validity ofan advance directive, as Mr C had to do. None theless, advance directives are generally recognized asan important part of patient choice and auton-omy. Although they no longer apply only to termi-nal conditions, as they did when first introducedin the United States during the late 1970s, theymay be particularly important in planning a treat-

16 End of life decision-making

Page 22: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

ment programme for dying people. In the US thereare both ‘information directives’ which specifywhat treatments are not acceptable to the patientand ‘proxy directives’ which authorize anotherindividual to make the decision.

Advance directives also illustrate the differencebetween acts and omissions in another sense.They cannot direct the clinician to undertake actsagainst his or her clinical judgement: only torefrain from treatment which the patient findsunacceptable. Resource limitations will alsodetermine what an advance directive can specify.Someone dying of kidney failure cannot obtaindialysis or a kidney transplant merely by takingout an advance directive demanding it. Englishcase law has held that there is no specific liabilityon the Secretary of State to provide any particularlevel of health care (ex parte Hincks, 1980).Furthermore, an advance directive cannot directwhat is unlawful. Thus in the UK at present, noone can take out an advance directive requestingeuthanasia or assisted suicide. The position in theNetherlands is different in relation to euthanasia,as we shall see in the next section.

Section 4. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide

Can euthanasia and physician-assisted suicideever be a rightful part of the goals of medicine?Can it ever be ethical to inflict death in the nameof avoiding suffering? Or is this a violation of themoral integrity of medicine (Singer and Siegler,1990; Pellegrino, 1992; Momeyer, 1995)? Can ‘thebest interests of the patient’ extend to ceasing toexist, or is that logically impossible? Is trust in themedical profession so radically undermined if

doctors are allowed to kill that we ought to ruleout euthanasia and physician-assisted suicidealtogether? Or does the possibility of euthanasiaand of assisted suicide where suffering is intract-able actually meet what patients want?

This section will explore these questions in thecontext of practice in the Netherlands, whereeuthanasia and assisted suicide are prohibited bythe Penal Code but may lawfully be performedif the doctor follows certain guidelines laid downby the courts and the medical profession. Thoseguidelines, and Dutch public opinion about eutha-nasia and physician-assisted suicide, were severelytested in a case involving a doctor who assisted thesuicide of an otherwise healthy woman who wasdeeply depressed over the deaths of her two sons:the case of Dr Boudewyn Chabot (Berghmans,1997a). Dr Chabot felt that he would be letting hispatient down, and increasing her suffering, if hefailed to grant her request for assisted suicide. Hisdeep commitment to his patient – which no onequestioned – led him to feel that assisting hersuicide was indeed part of his medical duty, and ofthe goals of medicine as he construed them.

Chabot’s critics, however, denied that he wouldbe failing in his duty to the patient if he refusedher request. It was also argued that the Chabotcase dramatically illustrated the ‘slippery slope’argument against euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: that once introduced, it allowsphysicians to ‘kill off’ patients who are not termi-nally ill, and indeed not even ill at all. At most, DrChabot’s patient was mentally ill, clinicallydepressed; but should such a request from a men-tally ill patient be respected? This relates back tothe C case, which you examined in the previoussection, and to the criteria for competence.

In this section we concentrate on a furtherextract from Ron Berghmans’s article on‘Physician-assisted suicide in the case of mentalsuffering’, which you began reading in Section 1.This part of the paper concerns the Chabot caseexplicitly, but it also sets that case in the widercontext of euthanasia and physician-assistedsuicide in Dutch practice. Before you begin, youshould note the difference between the two:

Euthanasia and assisted suicide 17

ACTIVITY: Take a few moments to write down the

key points raised by this section.

Page 23: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

• In physician-assisted suicide, the doctor pro-vides the means and guidance, e.g. a prescrip-tion for a lethal dose of medicine, andcounselling on doses and methods. Althoughthe physician may be present at the end, he orshe does not perform the final act: the patientdoes.

• In voluntary euthanasia, a physician adminis-ters a drug injection or other agent at thepatient’s request, thereby performing the finalact that results in the patient’s death(Berghmans, 1997a). Euthanasia is morecommon than physician-assisted suicide: about2.4 per cent of deaths in a recent Dutch researchproject resulted from euthanasia, against 0.3per cent from physician-assisted suicide. In 0.7per cent of cases, life was ended without theexplicit, concurrent request of the patient, eventhough in the Netherlands euthanasia is definedas voluntary euthanasia (Van der Maas et al.,1996). In many of these cases the patient wascomatose or otherwise incapable of making arequest. The Dutch Remmelink Commission of1992 estimated that up to 1000 instances ofeuthanasia every year were unasked for, andthat some of these included competentpatients. This is a frightening statistic, and, ifaccurate, a powerful argument against euthana-sia; but it is not our principal concern here.Rather, we proceed from the assumption, inarguendo, that euthanasia is valid whenrequested by a competent patient; but we testthat argument to the utmost by looking at a par-ticularly troubling case.

Now continue with your reading of Berghman’spaper.

Physician-assisted suicide in the caseof mental suffering

Ron Berghmans

The debate concerning physician-assisted suicideand euthanasia is broadening: along with patientssuffering from terminal illness, other groups of

patients are also being considered as potentialcandidates for assistance in dying. One of thesegroups is the mentally ill. I will concentrate on thecase of physician-assisted suicide for the mentallyill, offering some background to the debate con-cerning the practice of assisted suicide and eutha-nasia in the Netherlands, and presenting opinionas it is developing in the Dutch context.

Although the point is sometimes misunderstoodby foreign commentators, physician-assistedsuicide and euthanasia remain criminal offences inthe Netherlands. Assisting in the suicide of aperson, which includes providing the means forsomeone to take his life, is a crime under Article294 of the Penal Code. This article also applies tophysicians acting on the request of a patient(Gevers, 1995).

The legal acceptability of euthanasia andassisted suicide is based on recognition on a case-to-case basis of the physician’s defence of neces-sity (force majeure). To have this defenceaccepted, the doctor performing euthanasia orassisting with suicide must act according to thefive following criteria, as set down by the RoyalDutch Medical Association:(a) There must be a voluntary, competent and

enduring request on the part of the patient.(b) The patient’s request must be based on full

information.(c) The patient must be in a situation of intoler-

able and hopeless suffering.(d) All acceptable treatment alternatives must

have been attempted.(e) The physician must consult an independent

colleague before performing euthanasia orassisting with suicide.

We rated criterion (e) as the least problematic,and the easiest to prove or disprove in practice.(After you have read the case of Dr Chabot below,you might want to return to this list: you will seethat his case hinged on this factor.) The other four

18 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Which of these criteria would be the

easiest to fulfil, in your opinion, and which would be

the most problematic?

Page 24: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

criteria all seemed problematic to us for differentreasons.(a) How do we judge whether the doctor’s

influence lessens the voluntariness of theaction? What about patients who are unableto give a voluntary consent, because they arein a coma? We have already seen that there areinstances of euthanasia being performed onsuch patients in the Netherlands.

(b) Full information is almost never available: noone can say for certain how long the patientwill have to suffer. It is largely in B-grade filmsthat doctors give a definite estimate such as‘You only have six months to live’.

(c) The same caveat applies to ‘hopeless’. Thepalliative care movement would deny that anysuffering is ‘hopeless’; palliation can almostalways be achieved. Does ‘hopeless’ refer tothe possibility of cure or of good palliativecare?

(d) ‘No acceptable treatment alternatives’ begsthe question, insofar as the existence ofeuthanasia itself contaminates this decision.If it weren’t available, the patient couldn’t ruleout all other alternatives.

These requirements were developed in thecontext of persons suffering from a terminal, or atleast fatal or incurable, disease, such as patientswith advanced cancer (Gevers, 1995). In the1980s and 1990s, through a series of court deci-sions, reports and opinions from bodies such asthe Dutch Society of Psychiatrists, the Royal DutchSociety of Medicine, the Inspectorate for MentalHealth, and the Dutch Association for VoluntaryEuthanasia, attention was extended to the issueof physician-assisted suicide for psychiatricpatients. Lower courts took the view that, inexceptional circumstances, assisting a mentally illperson to commit suicide might be acceptablepractice.

A landmark in this respect has been the so-called Chabot case (Griffiths, 1995). The defendantwas a psychiatrist named Boudewyn Chabot, whoin September 1991 supplied to Mrs Boomsma, ather request, lethal drugs which she consumed in

the presence of the defendant, her GP, and afriend. She died half an hour later.

Mrs Boomsma was 50 years old; she hadmarried at 22, but from the beginning the mar-riage was unhappy. In 1986 her eldest son com-mitted suicide. From that time on her maritalproblems grew worse and her husband moreviolent; her wish to die began to take shape, butshe said that she remained alive only to care forher younger son. In 1988 she left her husband,taking her younger son with her. In 1990 her sonwas admitted to hospital in connection with atraffic accident, and was found to be sufferingfrom cancer, from which he died in May 1991.That same evening Mrs Boomsma attemptedsuicide with drugs she had put by, but did not die.She then approached the Dutch Association forVoluntary Euthanasia, which put her in touch withDr Chabot.

Mrs Boomsma was diagnosed as suffering froman adjustment disorder, consisting of a depressedmood, without psychotic signs, in the context of acomplicated bereavement process. Although hercondition was in principle treatable, treatmentwould probably have been protracted and thechance of success small. But she rejected therapy,despite Dr Chabot’s best efforts to persuade her.He became convinced that she was experiencingintense, long-term psychic suffering which wasunbearable for her, and which held out no pros-pect of improvement. Her request for assistancewith suicide in his opinion was well considered. Inletters and discussion with him, she presented thereasons for her decision clearly and consistently,showing that she understood her situation and theconsequences of her decision. In his judgement,her rejection of therapy was also well considered.Chabot consulted seven experts. None of thembelieved that there was any realistic chance ofsuccess, given Mrs Boomsma’s clear refusal oftreatment.

In its ruling of 21 June 1994, the DutchSupreme Court used the Chabot case to clarify anumber of important issues in the euthanasiadebate. First, it held that assistance with suicidewas justified in the case of a patient whose

Euthanasia and assisted suicide 19

Page 25: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

suffering is not somatic, and who is not in the ter-minal phase of an illness – but only if the physi-cian has acted ‘with the utmost carefulness’. Thecourt took the view that what matters is the seri-ousness of the patient’s suffering, not its source.

Secondly, the court stated that it was incorrect,as a general legal proposition, to claim that apsychiatric patient’s request for assistance withsuicide cannot be voluntary. A person’s wish to diecan be based on an autonomous judgement, evenin the presence of mental illness.

The basic proposition appears similar on thesurface: both courts agree that mental illness doesnot in itself bar a patient from making a validmedical decision. If you believe that killing isdifferent from letting die, however, the Chabotcase is more serious: Dr Chabot was being askednot to refrain from doing everything which couldbe done, but to actively assist Mrs B in her suicide– an act rather than an omission. There is alsoconsiderable doubt about whether Mrs B actuallywas mentally ill, or simply grief-stricken –whereas there is no doubt that C was the victim ofgross psychotic delusions. Finally, in Englishmental health law a patient is allowed to refusetreatment for a physical disorder, but not treat-ment for mental disorder. The C case is consistentwith that principle. Mrs Boomsma, however, hadrejected treatment designed to mitigate herdepression, that is, treatment concerning hermental health. It is certainly arguable that, if shewas adjudged mentally ill, she should have beenforcibly treated by anti-depressant medication. Ifshe was not mentally ill, but rather deeplybereaved and yet sane, there were no medicalgrounds for assisting her suicide.

The Supreme Court also took the view that apatient’s condition cannot be considered hopelessif he or she freely rejects a meaningful treatmentoption. In such a case, assisted suicide is notjustified. The difficult question is what counts as a

meaningful option. The court followed the view-point of a committee of the Dutch Royal Collegeof Medicine, which laid down the following threeconditions:• the patient’s condition can be alleviated if

proper treatment is given, on current medicalopinion

• alleviation is possible within a reasonable timeperiod

• the relationship of benefits to burdens of treat-ment should be proportionate.

Finally, the Supreme Court took the view that anindependent expert must be consulted on all rele-vant aspects of the case, and must himselfexamine the patient before assistance with suicidecan be given. This was the respect in whichChabot was adjudged to have failed. The sevenexperts whom he consulted had not themselvesexamined the patient. Therefore Chabot was con-victed by the Court, although he was given asuspended sentence. After the Supreme Courtdecision, Chabot was also cautioned by the DutchMedical Council, which took the view that heshould have considered treating his patient withanti-depressants, even if she refused consent.

Two large-scale research projects into the practiceof medical decision-making at the end of life haveprovided reliable data on the types of decisionsbeing made, the motives of physicians, and othercharacteristics of Dutch practice on euthanasia andassisted suicide (Van der Maas et al., 1991, 1996).Another project, conducted in 1996, after theSupreme Court ruling in the Chabot case, alsogives insight into the incidence of physician-assisted death in psychiatric practice (Groenewoudet al., 1997). Explicit requests for physician-

20 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: How does this judgement compare with

the C case we considered earlier?

ACTIVITY: The implication of the Dutch Medical

Council ruling is that most psychiatrists would have

treated Mrs Boomsma with anti-depressants, and

that Dr Chabot’s decision was aberrant practice. But

how often do such cases arise? If they are rare, how

can we know what is typical practice? – and how

useful is the Chabot case for ‘ordinary practice’? How

common do you think such cases are?

Page 26: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

assisted suicide are not uncommon in psychiatricpractice, but these requests are rarely granted. Onthe basis of Groenewoud’s data, we can estimatethat physician-assisted suicide in psychiatric prac-tice occurs two to five times per year in theNetherlands. The total incidence of explicitrequests for physician-assisted suicide by psychiat-ric patients was estimated to be about 320 annu-ally. Most of the psychiatric patients who receivedsuicide assistance suffered from both a mental dis-order and a serious physical illness (unlike MrsBoomsma, who was physically well). The most fre-quently mentioned reasons for assisting in suicidewere that the patient’s suffering was unbearableor hopeless, and that all previous treatment hadfailed. Two-thirds of Dutch psychiatrists surveyedconsider assisted suicide in mental illness to beacceptable, and 46 per cent could envisage a casein which they themselves would be prepared toassist the patient in suicide.

After the Supreme Court’s ruling in the Chabotcase, the Dutch Society of Psychiatrists establisheda committee to advise on guidelines for dealingwith requests for assisted suicide by patients whosuffer from mental illness. The committee beganfrom the following premises:• A request for assistance in suicide in someone

with mental illness ought to be assumed to be arequest for help. The presumption should bethat suicidal wishes are a sign of psychopathol-ogy, in the first instance, requiring suicide pre-vention, not suicide assistance.

A request for suicide assistance from a terminally illpatient should always be considered a reflection of badpractice. There is something wrong with the diagnosticor therapeutic process which has led to such a strongrefusal to carry on with life (Bracalenti and Mordini,1997).

Bracalenti and Mordini do not confine their state-ment to patients with mental illness: that is a key

difference from the Dutch guidelines. However, inboth cases clinicians are advised to make a primafacie assumption against honouring a request forsuicide. But the Dutch psychiatrists’ associationgoes on to state that:

• Suicidality should not a priori be considered as apsychopathological phenomenon. Although manydeath wishes in mentally ill people have a temporary,transitory character, in exceptional cases a request forsuicide assistance may be the result of a careful weigh-ing process, and may be enduring.

• In exceptional cases, physician-assisted suicide maybe responsible practice, but it can never be a generalduty. Individual psychiatrists have no moral or legalobligation to practise assisted suicide, although theydo have a duty to deal responsibly and carefully withevery request for suicide assistance.

There is no duty to kill implied in the relief ofsuffering, nor in the patient’s right to die. As theAmerican bioethicist Daniel Callahan succinctlyputs it, ‘Your right to die doesn’t imply my duty tokill’.

The Chabot case illustrates the ‘slippery slope’problem about euthanasia and physician-assistedsuicide, in that it seems unlikely that this was thesort of case envisioned when the current guide-lines were first established (Keown, 1995a, 1997).Have the Dutch gone too far? Within theNetherlands, the Chabot case occasioned wide-spread doubts to that effect. Outside the country,some commentators even surmised the Chabot

Euthanasia and assisted suicide 21

ACTIVITY: Compare this premise with the argu-

ment made below by two medically trained practising

psychoanalysts from Italy, Raffaele Bracalenti and

Emilio Mordini:

ACTIVITY: What does this imply about goals of

medicine? Think back to the original premise with

which this chapter began, that the principal goal of

medical care at the end of life is the relief of suffering.

Throughout this section we have been testing that

premise to the utmost, by asking whether it is a duty

in cases of hopeless and unbearable suffering to

relieve that suffering by assisting the patient to die.

On this alternative view, relieving suffering by assist-

ing suicide is not part of the telos of medicine; rather,

the proper goal is to deal carefully and responsibly

with any request for suicide, and thereby to take the

patient and her suffering seriously.

Page 27: Casestudies commentaries andactivitiescatdir.loc.gov/catdir/samples/cam033/00042939.pdf · had the physician agreed with the family’s request for the withdrawal of all kinds of

cases demonstrated that euthanasia and physi-cian-assisted suicide risk becoming a kind ofsocial control and medical abuse (Bracalenti andMordini, 1997). If there was no medical problemin Mrs Boomsma’s case, this argument runs, itbecomes clear that Chabot’s action instantiatessocial rather than medical judgements. If we lookat a hypothetical case of a healthy 50-year-oldIndian woman who ‘requests’ suttee on herbereavement, surely we would think this aninstance of dreadful social pressure, not a freechoice.

Terminal illness, however, had never been arequirement in the Dutch system, and it can cer-tainly be argued that mental suffering is no lessunendurable than physical pain. Although mentalillness may undermine autonomy and compe-tence – thereby casting the request for euthanasiafrom a mentally ill person into doubts aboutvalidity – it does not automatically make the deci-sion to refuse treatment invalid, as we saw in theC case.

On the other hand, by focusing on the doctor’sduties rather than the patient’s competence, itbecomes irrelevant as to whether Mrs B’s illnesswas mental or physical. As one of his criticspointed out at the Dutch Medical Associationhearing, if Mrs B was mentally well enough tomake a valid request for physician-assistedsuicide, Dr Chabot, as a psychiatrist, should nothave been acting in the first place. (Although healso viewed himself as her friend, he would havehad no access to the lethal drugs if he were actingmerely in his private capacity.) If Mrs B was men-tally ill, Dr Chabot’s duty was to cure her mentalillness rather than assist her suicide. In fact DrChabot recognized that Mrs B was not mentallyill; the ‘illness’ from which she suffered wasintractable grief. But that takes us back to thequestion of whether euthanasia was intended as a‘remedy’ for human tragedy. Surely not – and ifnot, then this case shows that the Dutch haveindeed slid too far down the slope.

A different sort of argument against euthanasiaand physician-assisted suicide draws attention tothe regrettable practical consequences of focusing

on its legalisation, rather than pressing forimprovements in palliative care. This view, typicalof the hospice movement, asserts that proponentsof euthanasia and assisted suicide encourage thewidespread public misapprehension that nothingcan be done about suffering at the end of lifeexcept to end it by death. This is pernicious, theyargue, and indeed ethically wrong. In the nextsection we will look at an example of good pallia-tive care and dialogue with the patient. Thepurpose of this example is twofold: to provide anordinary case from everyday hospice practice, incontrast to the highly dramatic and unusual caseof Dr Chabot, and to show how doctors mayrespond to what their patients want withoutfeeling, as Dr Chabot did, that he would be lettinghis patient down if he did not assist her suicide.

Section 5: Ethics at the end oflife: a case

We began this chapter on ethical issues at the endof life with a consideration of the telos of medicineand of the role of the physician in situationswhere it seemed clear that ‘healing’ was no longerpossible. In the introductory section we made thetentative hypothesis that the telos of medicineunder these circumstances might perhaps best becharacterized as something like the ‘alleviation ofsuffering’. As you have worked your way throughthe various sections of the chapter since then, wehave asked you to consider whether this is in factan adequate expression of the ethical dimensionsof decision-making in palliative care. Together, wehave explored what the ethical and practicalimplications of this conceptualization might bethrough the consideration of a range of ‘hardcases’.

22 End of life decision-making

ACTIVITY: Take a few moments to list the key

points from this section.