Purity Benjamin Kant

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    1/10

    Purity (Benjamin with Kant)

    Carlo Salzani *

    Centre for Comparative Literature and Cultural Studies, Monash University, Victoria 3800, Australia

    Around 1921 Benjamin wrote three seminal essays: Critique of

    Violence [Zur Kritik der Gewalt] commenced at the end of 1920,

    completed in January 1921 (cf. GB 2:131)1 and published in issue 3

    (August 1921) of theArchiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik;

    The Task of the Translator [Die Aufgabe des Ubersetzers], written in

    Autumn 1921 and published in October 1923 as foreword of

    Benjamins own translation of BaudelairesTableaux parisiens; and

    Goethes Elective Affinities [Goethes Wahlverwandtschaften],

    probably composed between Autumn 1921 and Summer 1922,

    and published in two issues of Hofmannsthals Neue Deutsche

    Beitrage (the first part in April 1924 and the second in January

    1925). The three essays, though devoted to different subjects,

    present nonetheless a certain unity of tone and a sort of kinship in

    the recurrence of some fundamental themes of Benjamins early

    theorisation, like myth, representation, morality, law and lan-

    guage. One peculiar notion holds them together, not only because

    it constitutes, in a sense, the kernel of the respective analyses, butalso insofar as the way this notionis theorised in eachof the essays

    can help explain its significance for the other two:purity [Reinheit].

    In Critique of Violence, it informs the politics of pure means

    [reines Mittel] construed around the notion of pure violence [reine

    Gewalt]; in The Task of the Translator, it is present in pure

    language [reine Sprache], a notion which informs also the Goethe

    essay,wherepurity does notexplicitly appear, butis implicit in the

    form of the expressionless [das Ausdruckslose]; in turn, the notion

    of the expressionless can be connected back to the essay on

    violence, since it is identified with critical violence [kritische

    Gewalt] andendowedwithmoralsignificance. It is noteworthy that

    History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447

    A R T I C L E I N F O

    Article history:

    Available online 21 August 2010

    Keywords:

    Purity

    Walter Benjamin

    Immanuel Kant

    Critique

    Violence

    Ethics

    A B S T R A C T

    The essay analyses the notion of purity in the early writings of Walter Benjamin, focusing more

    specifically on three essays written around the crucial year 1921: Critique of Violence, The Task of the

    Translator, and Goethes Elective Affinities. In these essays, purity appears in the notions of pure

    means,pure violence, pure language,and, indirectly, the expressionless. The essay argues, on the onehand, that the purity of these concepts is one and the same notion, and, on the other, that it is strongly

    indebted to, if not a by-product of, Kants theorisation of the moral act. In order to make this claim, the

    essay analyses Benjamins intense engagement with Kants writings in the 1910s and early 1920s:

    purity is a category strongly connoted within the philosophical tradition in which the young Benjamin

    moved his first steps, namely Kantian transcendental criticism. The essay argues that the notion of

    purity in Benjamin, though deployed outside and often against Kants theorisation and that of his

    followers, and moreover influenced by different and diverse philosophical suggestions, retains a strong

    Kantian tone, especially in reference to its moral and ethical aspects. Whereas Benjamin rejects Kants

    model of cognition based on the purity of the universal laws of reason,and thus also Kants theorisation

    of purity as simply non empirical and a priori, he models nonetheless his politics and aesthetics around

    suggestions that arise directly from Kants theorisation of the moral act and of the sublime, and uses a

    very Kantian vocabulary of negative determinations construed with the privatives-los and -frei (motiv-

    frei, zweck-los, gewalt-los, ausdrucks-los, intention-frei, etc). The essay explores thus the connections

    that link pure means, pure language and pure violence to one another and to the Kantian tradition.

    2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    * Corresponding author. Tel.: +49 151 576 85135 (mobile); fax: +49 228 73 3986.

    E-mail addresses: [email protected],[email protected] All references to Benjamins and Kants works are made parenthetically in the

    text. Allreferences to Benjamins works areprovidedboth to theGerman text of the

    Gesammelte Schriften (Collected Writings), ed. Rolf Tiedemann, Hermann Schwep-penhauser, 7 vols. in 15 (Frankfurt am Main, 19721989), or theGesammelte Briefe

    (Collected Letters), ed. Christoph Godde, Henri Lonitz, 6 vols. (Frankfurt am Main,

    19952000) (hereafter cited as GS and GB, respectively), and to the English

    translation of theSelected Writings, ed. Marcus Bullock,Michael W. Jennings,4 vols.

    (Cambridge, MA, 19962003) andThe Origin of German Tragic Drama, Trans. John

    Osborne (London & New York, 1998) (hereafter cited asSWand OT, respectively).

    When no English translation is available, I will use my own. All references to Kants

    works are provided both to the German text of the Werke (Works), ed. Wilhelm

    Weischedel, 6 vols. (Darmstadt, 1956ff), and to the following English translations:

    Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals, Trans.Thomas KingsmillAbbott

    (Mineola, NY, 2005); Critique of Practical Reason, trans. Thomas Kingsmill Abbott

    (Mineola, NY, 2004);The Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Mary Gregor (Cambridge,

    1996); Critique of Judgement, Trans. J.H. Bernard (Mineola, NY, 2005)(hereaftercited

    as GMS, KPV, MSand KU, respectively).

    Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

    History of European Ideas

    j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / h i s t e u r o i d e a s

    0191-6599/$ see front matter 2010 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

    doi:10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.07.003

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.07.003mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/01916599http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.07.003http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.07.003http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/01916599mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.histeuroideas.2010.07.003
  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    2/10

    the three essays were written within little more than a year, and

    the recurrence of purity in them cannot therefore be merely

    coincidental. In other words, it can be argued that the purity of

    pure means, pure language and pure violence is one and the same

    notion.

    Purity is also, however, a category strongly connotedwithin the

    philosophical tradition in which the young Benjamin moved his

    first steps, namely Kantian transcendental criticism. It is my

    contention that the notion of purity in Benjamin, though deployed

    outside and often against Kants theorisation and that of his

    followers, and moreover influenced by different and diverse

    philosophical suggestions, retains a strong Kantian tone, especially

    in reference to its moral and ethical aspects. Whereas Benjamin

    rejects Kants model of cognition based on the purity of the

    universal laws of reason, andthus also Kants theorisationof purity

    as simply non empirical and a priori, he models nonetheless his

    politics and aesthetics around suggestions that arise directly from

    Kants theorisation of the moral act and of the sublime, and uses a

    very Kantian vocabulary of negative determinations construed

    with the privatives-los and -frei (motiv-frei, zweck-los, gewalt-los,ausdrucks-los, intention-frei, etc).2 In what follows, I will attempt to

    illustrate the meaning ofpurity in Benjamins three essays and to

    explore the connections that link them to one another and to the

    Kantian tradition.

    Pure means

    In Critique of Violence Benjamin proposes a politics of pure

    means that would interrupt the instrumental cycle of means-ends

    characteristic of Western moral and political thought. The first

    paragraph of the essay situates violence in the realm of means, but

    at the same time disavows any critique that sought in a system of

    just ends its criterion of judgment, for it would merely constitute a

    criterion for the uses of violence, and not for violence itself as a

    principle. Rather, a critique of violence must seek its criterion

    within the sphere of means themselves, without regard for the

    ends they serve

    3

    (GS2.1:179/SW1:236). Benjamin proposes thusto separate means from their natural, instrumental connection to

    ends, exclude the realm of ends and the question of justice from its

    critique, andexplicitly limit the latterto thequestionof violence as

    means in its relation to morality.4 Pure means are put forward, in

    this context, as the only possible non-violent instance of conflict

    resolution, one that would disengage violence from its law-making

    and law-preserving character and from law in general.5 Their

    subjective preconditions are located in the culture of the heart

    [Kultur des Herzens], in courtesy, sympathy, peaceableness, trust

    [Herzenshoflichkeit, Neigung, Friedensliebe, Vertrauen], but their

    objective manifestation is restricted to indirect resolution

    [mittelbarer Losung], to matters concerning objects [Sachen]:

    The sphere of non-violent means opens up in the realm of human

    conflicts relating to goods,6 and this means that Technik is their

    proper sphere. As example of this technique Benjamin singles out

    the conference or interlocution [die Unterredung], and thus

    language as the sphere of human agreement absolutely inacces-

    sible to violence (GS2.1:1912/SW1:2445). Other examples are

    the proletarian general strike as described by Geroges Sorel,

    educativepower [erzieherische Gewalt], whichin itsperfected form

    stands outside the law7 (GS2.1:200/SW1:250), and the task of

    diplomats, since, analogously to the agreement between private

    persons, they must proceed case by case and without contracts,

    and their actions is thus beyond all legal systems and therefore

    beyond violence8 (GS2.1:193, 195/SW1:245, 247).

    The notion of pure means, of means purified of their ends, is,

    however, highly paradoxical. As Peter Fenves notes, means are by

    definition dependent on the idea of end, they are such only if they

    serve certain ends; whereas the notion of pure ends inhabits the

    Western philosophical tradition, from Aristotle to Kant, means

    cannot be easily made independent. Pure ends, or, in Kants

    definition, ends-in-themselves, are those which are independent

    of means, which find their own perfection in themselves as in

    Aristotle and are therefore im-mediate and ab-solute, separatedby the means necessary to achieve them. Pure means cannot, in

    this sense, be considered means-in-themselves, since to be in

    itself means to be as its own end.9 However, the traditional,

    syllogistic10 relationship between means and ends, and specifi-

    cally in thecontext of a critique of violence as a means,presents for

    Benjamin a constitutive ambiguity [Zweideutigkeit]: the formal

    freedom guaranteed by law remains indissolubly bound to the

    guilt to which the law inevitably sentences life.11 Moreover, the

    existence of thelegal order [das Recht], the realm in which violence

    is deployed as a means to the higher ends of civil cohabitation, is

    sustained in fact not by the intention of preserving legal ends but,

    rather, by the intention of preserving the law itself12 (GS2.1:183/

    SW 1:239). This constitutive ambiguity of the law is called by

    Benjamin mythic,13

    the very same ambiguity which characterisesthe pronouncements of fate and is the final reason for the

    ultimate insolubility of all legal problems14 (GS 2.1:196/SW

    1:247). To the contrary, the definition of morality must be free of

    any ambiguity, andfrom this derives the necessity of dissolving the

    mutual implication of means and ends.15 By assigningto God alone

    the determination of the justness of ends Benjamin dismantles the

    connection between the realm of just ends and the question of

    justified means, and thus from any possible law, whose generali-

    2 A similar argument is put forward by Benjamin Morgan; however, Morgan

    focuses on Benjamins (and Agambens) debt to the Kantian aesthetics for the

    development of the politics of pure means, whereas I argue that this aesthetics is

    also strictly related to the theorisation of the moral act. Cf. B. Morgan, UndoingLegal Violence: Walter Benjamins and Giorgio Agambens Aesthetics of Pure

    Means, Journal of Law and Society 34.1 (March 2007), 4664.3 in der Sphare der Mittel selbst, ohne Ansehung der Zwecke, denen sie dienen.4 The realm of ends, and therefore also the question of a criterion of justness, are

    excluded forthe time being from this study.Instead, thecentral place is given to the

    question of the justification of certain means that constitute violence [Das Bereich

    der Zwecke und damit auch die Frage nach einem Kriterium der Gerechtigkeit schaltet

    fur diese Untersuchung zunachst aus. Dagegen fallt in ihr Zentrum die Frage nach der

    Berechtigung gewisser Mittel, welche die Gewalt ausmachen] ( GS2.1:181/SW1:237).5 All violence as a meansis eitherlawmakingor law-preserving.If itlays claim to

    neither of these predicates, it forfeits all validity. It follows, however, that all

    violence as a means, even in the most favourable case, is implicated in the

    problematic nature of law itself [Alle Gewalt ist als Mittel entweder rechtsetzend oder

    rechtserhaltend. Wenn sie auf keines dieser beiden Pradikate Anspruch erhebt, so

    verzichtetsie damitselbstauf jedeGeltung.Darausaber folgt, dassjede Gewalt alsMittel

    selbst im gunstigsten Falle an der Problematik des Rechts uberhaupt teilhat] (GS

    2.1:190/SW 1:243).

    6 In dersachlisten Beziehungmenschlicher Konflikte auf Gutereroffnet sich das Gebiet

    der reinen Mittel.7 in ihrer vollendeten Form auerhalb des Rechts steht.8 jenseits aller Rechtsordnung und also Gewalt.9

    Cf. P. Fenves, Out of the Order of Number: Benjamin and Irigaray toward aPolitics of Pure Means, Diacritics, 28.1 (Spring 1998), 467.10 B. Hanssen, Critique of Violence: Between Poststructuralism and Critical Theory

    (London and New York, 2000), 20.11 Cf. G. Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, Zur

    Theorie der Gewalt und Gewaltlosigkeitbei Walter Benjamin (Heidelberg,1979), 910.12 das Interesse des Rechts an der Monopolisierung der Gewalt gegenuber der

    Einzelperson sich nicht durch die Absicht erklare, die Rechtszwecke, sondern vielmehr

    durch die, das Recht selbst zu wahren.13 Here appear, in a terribly primitive form, the mythic ambiguity of laws that

    may not be infringed the same ambiguity to which Anatole France refers

    satirically when he says, Poor and rich are equally forbidden to spend the night

    under the bridges [Hiermit tritt in furchtbarer Ursprunglichkeit dieselbe mythische

    Zweideutigkeit der Gesetze, die nicht ?ubertreten werden durfen, in Erscheinung, von

    der Anatole France satirisch spricht, wenn er sagt: Sie verbieten es Armen und Reichen

    gleichermaen, unter Bruckenbogen zu nachtigen] (GS 2.1:198/SW 1:249).14 die letztlichen Unentscheidbarkeit aller Rechtsprobleme.15

    Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel , 910.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447 439

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    3/10

    sation [Verallgemeinerung] contradicts the nature of justice (GS

    2.1:196/SW1:247).

    What characterises then pure means? Gunter Figal identifies

    three main traits: firstly, they are qualified as non-violent, as what

    interrupts the mythical cycle of violence and retribution that

    characterises the legal order. Purity is thus an indicator of this

    absence,of this interruption,a purificationfrom.16 Secondly, they

    are not justifiedby any end or purpose,their purity is not derived

    from just ends, but by their absence. They reject thus the very

    notion of instrumentality and can be qualified asnon-instrumen-

    tal.17 Finally, they cannot be identified with any action that finds

    its origin in a subject and are thus subject-less, purified from the

    notion of subject itself: as Technik of indirect resolution, they

    relate rather to objects, and this means that their morality is

    independent purified from any determinable will. What

    morality they present must lie in themselves. Thesetraits make for

    the medial character of pure means.18 The sphere of mediacy is

    therefore the realm of pure means: ends situated outside this

    sphere, and which would claim to be removed from, and superior

    to it, would only mask in their ambiguity the historicity of their

    determination. Werner Hamacher emphasises that mediacy as

    mediation, transitionor transmittal,precedes in a certainsensethe

    two extremes it links: as a form of interpersonality, it does not

    haveas its initiator andits addressee already constitutedsubjects,but [. . .] from the outset constitutes them as mediated.19 This

    mediacy, Hamacher continues,is theconditionof possibility of the

    transition between the two extremes, but at the same time is also

    its interruption: it works simultaneously as condition and

    caesura, as will become evident in the analysis of language as

    medium.20

    The rejection of the realm of just ends takes the Kantian ethics

    directly to task. Kants moral philosophy is in fact structuredon the

    circular relation between means and ends, upon which both

    natural and positive law are based: In Metaphysics of Morals

    [Metaphysik der Sitten, 1797], ethics is defined as the system of theendsof the pure practical reason21 (MS, A 5/146, emphasis in the

    original) and is based on the notion of just ends. When Benjamin

    states that a critique of violence cannot be implied in a system ofjust ends, for it would only contain the criterion for cases of the use

    of violence and not forviolence itselfas a principle, he disavows the

    systematic construction of the Kantian ethics (cf. GS2.1:179/SW

    1:236).22 Furthermore, by restricting to God alone therealm of just

    ends, Benjamin implicitly undermines the Kantian system based

    on the universality of reason, which constitutes the formal

    foundation of universal freedom23: For it is never reason that

    decides on thejustification of means andthe justness of ends: fate-

    imposed violence decides on the former, and God on the latter24

    (GS 2.1:196/SW 1:247, emphasis added). The paragraph that

    follows constitutes also a critique of the first formulation of the

    categorical imperative in the Fundamental Principles of the

    Metaphysics of Morals [Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten,

    1785] Act only on that maxim whereby thou canst at the same timewill that it should become a universal law25 (GMS, BA 52/38):

    generalization [Verallgemeinerung], which is the constitutive

    principle of law, contradicts the nature of justice26 (GS2.1:196/SW 1:247). Explicitly, then, Benjamin attacks the program

    established with the categorical imperative as minimalist and

    insufficient:the secondformulation of it act in such a waythat at

    alltimesyou usehumanity both in your personand in the personof

    all others as anend, and never merely as a means27 is inadequate

    insofar as positive law too if conscious of its roots28 does claim

    to acknowledgeand promote the interest of mankind in the person

    of each individual29 through the representation and preservation

    of the legal order. In seeking to recognise the interest of humanity

    in every individual, therefore, the law merely preserves an order

    imposed by fate [schicksalhaften Ordnung]. Moreover, Benjamin

    wonders whether this demand does not contain too little and

    whether it is permissible to use, or allow to be used, oneself or

    another in any respect as a means.30 He claims that good grounds

    could be adduced in favour of this point, but, as often happens in

    his work, we are left to wonder what these might be (GS2.1:187/SW1:241, 252).

    Pure will

    If Benjamins politics of pure means sets itself explicitly against

    the formal structure of Kants moral philosophy, its indebtednessto Kants theorisation must nonetheless be emphasised. This debt

    is usually acknowledged in the literature on Critique of Violence

    and on Benjamins early works more in general; however, the

    mention is too often limited to underline the fact that the essay

    starts off formally following the conventions of transcendental

    critique and finally opposes to Kants Enlightenment rationalism a

    messianism deep-rooted in the Jewish tradition.31 The early

    critical analysis of Gunter Figal and Horst Folkers investigates, on

    the contrary, Benjamins debt to the Kantian project, but has not

    enjoyed much echo.32 As Figal points out, Benjamins ethical

    construction in this early phase must be considered a modification

    of Kants moral philosophy, and a look back at Kants system

    becomes necessary in order to shed light on it.33 It is not only that

    Benjamin adopts Kants fundamental distinction between moralityand legality and disengages the morality of the act from the legal

    system; the relation is much deeper and fundamental. What

    particularlyinterests me here is the relation that links the notion of

    pure means to Kants theorisation of the moral act: in spite of

    Benjamins rejection of the Kantian ethics and especially of its

    dependence of the means-ends instrumentality, as well as of its

    Enlightenment rationalism and legalist metaphors, the notion of

    pure means is strongly indebted to, if not a by-product of, Kants

    theorisation of the moral act.

    16 Haxel Honnet restricts the meaning of purity mainly to this first trait. Cf. A.

    Honneth, Zur Kritik der Gewalt, Benjamin-Handbuch: Leben - Werk - Wirkung, ed.

    Burkhardt Lindner (Stuttgart, 2006), 204.17 Cf. Hanssen, Critique of Violence, 21.18 Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 112.19 W. Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, Cardozo Law Review (19911992), 1140.20 Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, 1141.21 System der Zwecke der reinen praktischen Vernunft.22 Cf. Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 6.23 Cf. Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 89.24 Entscheidet doch uber Berechtigung von Mitteln und Gerechtigkeit von Zwecken

    niemals dieVernunft, sondern schicksalhafte Gewalt uber jene, uber diese aber Gott.25 Handle nur nach derjenigen Maxime, durch die du zugleich wollen kannst, dass sie

    ein allgemeines Gesetz werde.

    26 was diesem Merkmal [der Gerechtigkeit] [...] widerspricht.27 handle so, dass Du die Menschheit sowohl in Deiner Person als in der Person eines

    jeden Anderen jederzeit zugleich als Zweck, niemals blo als Mittel brauchest.28

    wo es seiner Wurzeln sich bewusst ist.29 das Interesse der Menschheit in der Person jedes einzelnen anzuerkennen und zu

    fordern.30 ob es erlaubt sei, seiner selbst oder eines andern in irgendwelcher Hinsicht auch als

    eines Mittels sich bedienen zu lassen oder zu bedienen.31 Cf. for example B. Hanssen,Walter Benjamins Other History: Of Stones, Animals,

    HumanBeings,and Angels (Berkeley,1998), 130, and Hanssen,Critique of Violence, 3

    4. Michael Mack argues, against theusual assumptionof thecommentators,that the

    title Zur Kritik der Gewalt harksback notto theKantianmodelof critique,butrather

    to his friend Hugo Balls Zur Kritik der deutschen Intelligenz (1918), which highly

    criticised Kants theory of law. He acknowledges that Benjamin formally adopts

    Kants methodology, but emphasises how he radically undermines the latters

    theory of law as secularised Recht issuing not from God, but from autonomous

    reason. Cf. M. Mack, Between Kant and Kafka: Benjamins Notion of Law,

    Neophilologus85.2 (April 2001), 257.32 Cf. the two essays which constitute Gunter Figal and Horst Folkers, Zur Theorie

    der Gewalt und Gewaltlosigkeit bei Walter Benjamin (Heidelberg: FEST, 1979).33

    Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 2.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447440

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    4/10

    The roots of the politics of pure means must be sought in

    Benjamins intense engagement with Kants work during the

    1910s, which is testified by a series of fragments.34 The most

    complete document is The Moral Lesson [Der Moral Unterricht],

    published in July 1913 in Wynekens Die Freie Schulgemeinde, in

    which Benjamin takes a strong Kantian approach to ethics in

    relation to absolute pedagogical demands. Important for my

    argument is the fact that he emphasises a peculiar trait of Kants

    distinction between legality and morality: the fundamental

    determination of the moral will [sittliches Willen] is that it must

    bemotivfrei, free of any motivation, only determined by the moral

    law, which commands: act well35 (GS2.1:48). The goal of moral

    education is the creation of the moral will, he continues, but

    nothing is more inaccessible than this moral will, since as such it is

    no psychological variable, which could be achieved throughmeans36 (GS 2.1:49, emphasis added). The moral, pure will is as

    inaccessible to the educator as the pure and only valid moral law.

    In other words, the will is pure, and thus moral, as long as it is free

    of motivations and purposes, and so inaccessible to the means-

    ends logic and to subjectivity. The inaccessibility of the pure will

    through means, Figal points out, conversely implicates that the

    pure will cannot be conveyed or communicated [vermittelt]. The

    centre of Benjamins ethics is therefore, for Figal, the quest for a

    moral act (Gestaltgewinnung des Sittlichen, shaping of morality, inBenjamins words) that would not be a mediation or instrumen-

    tality [Vermittlung]. If the principle of morality is not communica-

    ble [vermittelbar], then the form of the moral act cannot be

    developed from the notion of means.37 The vocabulary of the

    politics of pure means is therefore already contained here in the

    play between the termsMittel (means; literally, what stands in the

    middle and thus as middle point between two extremes) andVer-

    mittlung (mediation, but also instrumentality), which will be

    echoed in the discussion ofMitteilbarkeit(communicability) in the

    language essays.

    Before turning to this point, however, I want to dwell a bit

    longer on the structure of Kants ethics. Howard Caygill underlines

    how the notion of purity in Kant is usually defined only

    negatively, thatis, as non-empirical38

    and, only as such, autonomousanda priori. Pure will [reines Willen], as defined in the Fundamental

    Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals , is thus one which should be

    determined solely froma priori principles without any empirical

    motives,39 andthe task of the metaphysicsof morals is preciselyto

    examine the idea and the principles of this pure will ( GMS, BA xii/

    5). Independent of what it performs or effects, and, most

    importantly, of some proposed end, that is, not merely good as

    ameansto something else, the good will must be good in itself[an

    sich]40 (GMS, BA 4, 6/10, 12). Consequently, a moral act, which is

    moral only insofar it is done from duty [aus Pflicht],

    derives its moral worth, not from the purpose which is to be

    attained by it, but from the maxim by which it is determined,

    andtherefore does not dependon therealizationof theobject of

    the action, but merely on the principle of volition by which the

    action has taken place, without regard to any object of desire.41

    (GMS, BA 14/16, emphases in the original)

    The foundation of the moral act is therefore always a self-

    foundation, it has no exterior and could not occur on the basis ofanything external to it:it is pure only insofarit arises from itself and

    is identical with the moral law. As such, it presents also no temporal

    exterior, that is, it must not be concerned with what comes after it

    and is beyond any criterion: it has no purpose outside itself and

    constitutes the only purpose of its ownrealisation. Thediscussionof

    the imperatives clarifies this point: whereas the hypothetical

    imperative represents the practical necessity of a possible action

    as means to something else that is willed (or at least which one

    might possibly will), the categorical imperative represents an

    action as necessary of itself without reference to another end, i.e., as

    objectively necessary42 (GMS, BA 40/31). In theCritique of Practical

    Reason [Kritik derpraktischenVernunft, 1788],Kant emphasises,then,

    that the necessity involvedin the moral lawis not of a physical type;

    rather,it can only consist in the formal conditions of the possibilityof the law in general43 (KPV, A 60/35). The paradox of this pure

    formalism consists in the fact that the concept of good and evil must

    notbedeterminedbeforethemorallaw(ofwhichitseemsasifitmustbe

    the foundation), but only after it and by means of it44 (KPV, A 110/66,

    emphasis in the original). What is essential in the moral worth of

    actions is thus that the moral law shoulddirectly determinethe will45

    (KPV, A 127/76, emphasis in the original).

    These determinations resound not only in Benjamins descrip-

    tion of the purity of means, but also, as we will see, in his

    theorisation of language as medium and in the moral value

    endowed to his notion of art criticism. This point does not,

    however, cushion Benjamins criticism to the Kantian system: Kant

    construes his moral philosophy aroundpure reasonand itstribunal

    and laws, anduses a language which insists obsessively on juridicalmetaphors; moreover, his notion of law is characterised byobjective universality and necessity, belongs to the Enlightenment

    master narrative of universal emancipation and ends up, inevita-

    bly, with a justification of the existent power. The Metaphysics of

    Moralsis not only based, both in the doctrine of right [Rechtslehre]

    and the doctrine of virtue [Tugendlehre], on the notion of end

    [Zweck], but finally legitimates the status quo (in the form of the

    unquestionability of law) and even authorises the use of

    coercion.46 Michael Mack argues that Kants political agenda,

    which finally justifies and affirms the authority of the immanent

    ruler, is founded on, and is a necessary by-product of, the

    immanentist justification of autonomous reason.47 Morality is34 Cf. GS 6, passim, especially the fragments of the section Zur Moral und

    Anthropologie.35

    einzig bestimmt durch das Sittengesetz, die Norm: handle gut.36 Und doch ist nichts unzuganglicher, als eben dieser sittlicher Wille, da er als solcher

    keine psychologische Groe ist, die man mit Mitteln behandeln k onnte.37 Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 45.38 In Kants philosophy pure is inevitably opposed to empirical, and both are

    aligned with a matrix of position which include form-matter, spontaneity-

    receptivity, autonomy-heteronomy, original-derived, condition-conditioned, pri-

    or-posterior, and a priori-a posteriori.[ . . .] Although it waswidely used by Kant,the

    concept itself is rarely thematized; Pure is often used synonymously with terms

    such as a priori, form, condition, autonomy and original, but its is also used to

    qualify these same terms as in pure a priori (KU, A 85=B 117). On some occasions

    a priori concepts and intuitions are pure because they are a priori; on others they

    area prioribecause they arepure.One of thefew pointsat which Kant approaches a

    self-sufficient definition of purity is in his equation of the pure and the original, H.

    Caygill,A Kant Dictionary (Oxford & Cambridge, MA, 1995), 341, 342.39 Eine solchen, der ohne alle empirische Bewegungsgrunde, vollig aus Prinzipien a

    priori, b estimmt werde.40

    Nicht etwa in anderer Absicht als Mittel, sondern an sich selbst guten Willen.

    41

    Eine Handlung aus Pflicht hat ihren moralischen Wertnicht in der Absicht,welchedadurch erreicht werden soll, sondern in der Maxime, nach der sie beschlossen wird,

    hangt also nicht von der Wirklichkeit des Gegenstandes der Handlung ab, sondern blo

    von dem Prinzip des Wollens, nach welchem die Handlung, unangesehen aller

    Gegenstande des Begehrungsvermogens, geschehen ist.42 Alle Imperativen nun gebieten entwederhypothetisch, oder kategorisch. Jene

    stellen die praktische Notwendigkeit einer moglichen Handlung als Mittel, zu etwas

    anderem,was manwill (oder doch moglich ist, dass man es wolle), zu gelangen, vor. Der

    kategorische Imperativ wurde der sein, welcher eine Handlung als fur sich selbst, ohne

    Beziehung auf einen andern Zweck, als objektiv-notwendig vorstellte.43 Kann also blo in formalen Bedingungen der Moglichkeit eines Gesetzes uberhaupt

    bestehen.44 Der Begriff des Guten und Bosen nicht vor dem moralischen Gesetze (dem es dem

    Anschein nach so gar zum Grunde gelegt werden musste), sondern nur (wie hier auch

    geschieht) nach demselben und durch dasselbe bestimmt werden musse.45 Das moralische Gesetz unmittelbar den Willen bestimme.46 Cf. for example the Introduction to the Doctrine of Right, E.47

    Mack, Between Kant and Kafka, 258.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447 441

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    5/10

    defined in relation to the laws of autonomous reason, in radical

    separation from the religious sphere; these laws are eternal,

    unquestionable and static and violence is only envisaged as a

    subversion of the rational order of things which the immanent law

    of the state must restrain.48 In the end, Mack writes, Kants

    autonomous reason works as a justification of the bourgeois state

    founded of the rationalisation of money and property: The

    violence of the law that upholds such a bourgeois and rational

    state of society must not be reasoned against, and thus law must

    preclude therevolutionaryviolence of those whorebel against it.49

    Moreover, by founding power on the universal and eternal laws of

    reason, Kant forbids any exploration into the origins of both state

    power and state law: the subjects of the state must not question

    the validity of the violence that enforces positive law; rather, they

    have to be aware of the debt they owe to the Recht.50 Benjamin,

    though formally adopting Kants transcendental method and the

    main character of his moral philosophy, undermines the idea of

    autonomous reason and substitutes it for his intense messianism.

    Macks argument leads to a fundamental point in the discussion

    of Benjamins politics of pure means: Benjamin takes issue with

    Kants ethics because the cognitive model on which it is founded,

    construed around the autonomy of reason, necessarily undermines

    the purity of the act and reinserts it into the means-ends cycle.

    Already in the 1914 essay on Holderlin, but more explicitly in the1918OntheProgramoftheComingPhilosophy[Uber dasProgramm

    der kommenden Philosophie], Benjamin labels Kants (and the Neo-

    Kantian) epistemology as mythical because it is based on the

    traditional subject-object divide, a conception that he was unable,

    ultimately, to overcome, despite all his attempts to do so51 (GS

    2.1:161/SW103). The task of future epistemology, he writes,

    is to find for knowledge the sphereof totalneutrality in regardto

    the concepts of both subject and object; in other words, it is to

    discover the autonomous, innate sphere of knowledge in which

    this concept in no way continues to designate the relation

    between two metaphysical entities.52 (GS2.1:163/SW1:104)

    The Kantian foundational myth the new epistemology mustovercome is precisely its methodological point of departure:

    subjectivity. It is this cognitive model that establishes the relation

    of instrumentality (Vermittlung) between the two metaphysical

    entities subject and object, and finally leads to the mythical

    circularity of means and ends. The rational subject of the Kantian

    tradition is confined within this circularity and the attempt to

    construe themoral acton theself-founding, pure will of thesubject

    fails insofar as it cannot overcome the divide. The great

    transformation and correction the coming philosophy should

    perform, Benjamin argues, can be attained only by relating

    knowledge to language, as was attempted by Hamann during

    Kants lifetime53 (GS2.1:168/SW 1:108). The conclusion of the

    Kants essay echoes, and refers to, the 1916 approach of the

    language essay and spells Benjamins large-scale plan, in Beatrice

    Hanssen words, to exchange the reflection model of the

    philosophy of consciousness for the insight of a full-fledged

    philosophy of language.54

    Pure language

    Benjamins philosophy of language is fundamental for an

    understanding of his politics of pure means. Not only because

    language is singled out, in Critique of Violence, as pure means,but

    also because of thefigure of pure language, which appears in both

    the 1916 On Language as Such and on the Language of Man [Uber

    Sprache uberhaupt und uber die Sprache des Menschen] and the 1921

    The Task of the Translator.

    Another important text, the famous letter Benjamin sent to

    Martin Buber on July 17, 1916, illustrates and emphasises the

    political implications of his philosophy of language and helps relate

    it to Critique of Violence. Benjamin writes to Buber in order to

    explainwhyhe willnot contribute tothe journal DerJude andcentres

    his argument on the political function of language. He rejects the

    common argument that the written word can influence the moral

    world and human action by providing motives for action because

    language is here considered merely a means [nur ein Mittel].

    Language as mere means [bloen Mittel] is rendered powerless

    [ohnmachtige] and debased [herabgewurdigte]; moreover, each

    action founded in the expansive tendency of the word-to-word

    sequence appears to me dreadful and all the more disastrous where

    this whole relation of word and deed increasingly spreads, as in our

    country, as a mechanism for the realisation of the right absolute.55

    The real impact and agency [Wirkung] of languagerests rather on its

    secret [Geheimnis], when it is considered poetic prophetic factual

    [dichterischprophetisch sachlich], or, ina wordwhich will recurin the

    language essay, magic, that is, im-mediate and un-mediated.56

    Effective [wirksam] is language not through the transmission of

    contents but rather through the pure revelation of its majesty and

    true essence,57 which takes place through the elimination of the

    ineffable [Elimination des Unsagbaren]: This elimination of the

    ineffable appears to me as coinciding precisely with the properly

    factual of pure writing and as intimating the relation between

    knowledge and action right within the linguistic magic.58 Only in

    this sense is language properly political [hochpolitisch]:notasmeans

    of an instrumental conception, but rather as leading towards that

    which theword withholds.59

    Benjamin insistson theterm Wirkung:really affective is languagewhen the word is intensely directed in

    the kernel of inner silence.60 Real [wirklich] actionis the wordin its

    purity[Reinheit] (GB1:3257).61

    This letter containsin nucethe fundamental trait of Benjamins

    language philosophy, developed then in the essay written in the

    same year: the mediality of language, or language as medium. The

    1916 language essay is construed around the play of a number of

    strictly related terms: Mitteilung, mitteilen and mitteilbar(com-

    munication, communicate and communicable), unmittelbar andUnmittelbarkeit(immediate and immediacy),MedialeandMedium

    (mediacy and medium). All communication of the contents of the

    mind, Benjamin states, is language; that is, language commu-

    nicates the mental being corresponding to it.62 However, this

    48 Mack, Between Kant and Kafka, 264.49 Mack, Between Kant and Kafka, 265.50 Mack, Between Kant and Kafka, 266.51 trotz aller Ansatze dazu nicht endgultig uberwundene Auffassung.52 Es ist die Aufgabe der kommenden Erkenntnistheorie fur die Erkenntnis die Sphare

    totaler Neutralitat in Bezug auf die Begriffe Objekt und Subjekt zu finden; mit andern

    Worten die autonome ureigne Sphare der Erkenntnis auszumitteln in der dieser Begriff

    auf keine Weise mehr die Beziehung zwischen zwei metaphysischen Entitaten

    bezeichnet.53 kann nur durch eine Beziehung der Erkenntnis auf die Sprache wie sie schon zu

    Kants Lebzeiten Hamann versucht hat gewonnen werden.54

    Hanssen,Walter Benjamins Other History, 30.

    55 Jedes Handeln das in der expansiven Tendenz des Wort-an-Wort-Reihens liegt

    scheint mir furchterlich und um so verheerender wo dieses ganze Verhaltnis von Wort

    undTat wiebei unsin immer steigendem Mae alsein Mechanismuszur Verwirklichung

    des richtigen Absoluten um sich greift.56 magisch das heit un-mittel-bar.57 nicht durch die Vermittlung von Inhalten sondern durch das reinste Erschlieen

    ihrer Wurde und ihres Wesens.58 Diese Elimination des Unsagbaren scheint mir gerade mit der eigentlich sachlichen

    der nuchternen Schreibart zusammenfallen und die Beziehung zwischen Erkenntnis und

    Tat eben innerhalb der sprachlichen Magie anzudeuten.59 hinzufuhren auf das dem Wort versagte.60 Nurdie intensiveRichtungder Worte inden Kern desinnersten Verstummenshinein

    gelangt zur wahren Wirkung.61 For a reading of this letter, cf. the excellent essay by S. Weber, Der Brief an

    Buber vom 17.7.1916,Benjamin-Handbuch, 6038.62

    teilt das ihr entsprechende geistige Wesen mit.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447442

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    6/10

    mental being communicates itself in language and not through

    language.63 In this sense, language has no speaker, is not a means

    for a subject to transmit any content. Language, Benjamin

    continues, communicates the linguistic being of things, but it is

    at the same time the clearest manifestation of this being, that is,

    that which is communicable in a mental entity; therefore, all

    language communicate itself64 (GS2.1:142/SW1:63). Language is

    not something external to the mental being, not a means to its

    communication. Put differently:

    All language communicates itself in itself; it is in the purest

    sense medium of the communication. Mediation, which is theimmediacy of all mental communication, is the fundamental

    problem of linguistic theory, and if one chooses to call this

    immediacy magic, then the primary problem of language is its

    magic.65 (GS2.1:1423/SW1:64, emphases in the original)

    Mediationis im-mediate, it is, as Figal puts it, identical with its

    presence.66 This notion of language asimmediate mediationrejects

    its instrumentality: it knows no means, no object, and no

    addressee of communication.67 There is no such a thing as a

    content of language: as communication, language communicates a

    mental entity something communicable per se

    68

    (GS2.1:1456/SW1:66, emphasis in the original). This means, as Werner Hamacher

    writes, that it precedes any performative utterance as a form of

    mediacy, and thus as sheer, preinstrumental technique. Impart-

    ing [Mitteilung], he continues, is a means which has no need of

    positing and which may underline any established linguistic

    political, or legal institution at any time. Language in its mediacy is

    pre-positional, preperformative and, in this sense, afformative.69

    Or, in Samuel Weber words, Unmittelbar(immediate[ly]) means

    not just immediate[ly] but also, more literally, without means or

    instrumentality. Language, in short, is to be understood not as a

    means to some other goal, but as the immediate possibility of

    being imparted.70 This possibility, then, is not to be intended as a

    Kantian formal condition of possibility, as Rodolphe Gasche notes,

    not as a subjective characteristic, but rather as a real possibility

    (dunamis) of potency in language.71 Weber acutely highlights

    another fundamental trait of the medium: it is not a means, but

    cannot be considered the opposite of a means either, that is, an end

    in itself; rather, it retains one decisive aspectof themeans, which is

    that it is not self-contained, complete, perfect or perfectible. It is

    simply there, but as somethingthat splits offfrom itself, takes leave

    of itself.72

    Language as medium is the name:

    The name is that throughwhich, and in which, language itself

    communicates itself absolutely. In the name, the mental entity

    that communicates itself is language.73 (GS2.1:144/SW65)

    It is only after the Fall, when name becomes human word[menschliches Wort], that language steps out of name-language and

    becomes a means: The word must communicatesomething(other

    than itself),74 but as such it looses the true knowledge of things

    and becomes prattle [Gescwatz]. In stepping outside the purer

    language of name,man makes language a means and therefore also

    a mere sign. An important consequence is that it is only after the

    Fall that judgement[das Gericht] becomes possible: knowledge of

    good and evil is in itself nameless [namenlos], is a knowledge from

    outside, which abandons the name (GS2.1:1523/SW1:71). In the

    Fall, man abandoned immediacy in the communication of the

    name and fell into the abyss of the mediateness of all

    communication, of the word as means, of the empty word, into

    the abyss of prattle.75 The very question of good and evil is in this

    sense prattle: The Tree of Knowledge stood in the garden of Godnot in order to dispense information on good and evil, but as an

    emblem of judgement over the questioner. This immense irony

    marks the mythic origin of law76 (GS2.1:154/SW1:72).

    Language as pure mediality is therefore prior to the judgement

    on good and evil, it is pure means, and this is why, Benjamin notes

    in Critique of Violence, fraud or deceit [Betrug] came only late

    under the sanction of law (cf. GS2.1:192/SW1:145). As medium

    and articulation of mediacy, language precedes any distinction

    between true and false and is not subject to it.77 On the same

    basis Benjamin distinguishes between compromise [Kompromi],

    diplomatic transactions, and conference or interlocution [Unterre-

    dung]: compromise remains embroiled within the means-ends

    logic and is therefore violent because, he quotes from Erich Unger,

    the effort toward compromise is motivatednot internally but from

    outside, by the opposing effort, because no compromise, however

    freely accepted, is conceivable without a compulsive character78

    (GS 2.1:191/SW 1:244). As such, Figal points out, compromise

    presents a law-positing character, oriented towards the realisation

    63 dieses geistige Wesen sich in der Sprache mitteilt und nichtdurchdie Sprache.64 jede Sprache teilt sich selbst mit.65 Jede Sprache teilt sich in sich selbst mit, sie ist im reinsten Sinne das ,,Medium der

    Mitteilung. Das Mediale, das ist die Unmittelbarkeit aller geistigen Mitteilung, ist das

    Grundproblem derSprachtheorie,und wennman dieseUnmittelbarkeit magisch nennen

    will, so ist das Urproblem der Sprache ihre Magie.66 Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, p. 12.67 kennt ... kein Mittel, keinen Gegenstand und keinen Adressaten der Mitteilung.68 Einen Inhalt der Sprache gibt es nicht; als Mitteilung teilt die Sprache ein geistiges

    Wesen, d.i. eine Mitteilbarkeit schlechthin mit.69 He continues: Even before and even during its performative effects, language

    does not initially lay the foundation for anything outside itself, but rather offers

    itselfas theform of mediacy between speakers,as their mediacy in a third entity, in

    a talk, anUnterredung, aninterof their languages, without which theywould not be

    language, Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, 11434.70 S. Weber,Benjamins -Abilities (Cambridge, MA/London, 2008), 117.71 R. Gasche, Saturnine Vision and the Question of Difference: Reflections of

    Walter Benjamins Theory of Language, Benjamins Ground: New Readings of Walter

    Benjamin, ed. RainerNagele (Detroit,1988),88. Therefore, rather than a category of

    possibility, communicabilityis constituted by things yearning to relateto theorigin

    of their creation in the Word. In language, in a verbal sense of their expression,

    things communicate that they are of divine origin. [. . .] But such yearning, such

    intention in language, is not subjective. Not things yearn to be heard: only that part

    of them that is spiritual, already linguistic the residue of the creative word does

    so. Communicability is, thus, anobjective(metaphysical) category that designates

    the difference that expression or language makes to the extent that as expression

    and language it communicates all by itself its difference, 89.

    72 He continues, stretching Benjamins theory in a strongly deconstructionist

    direction: Whatis immediate is thatwhich is defined by the potentiality of taking

    leave of itself, of its place and position, of altering itself. In thus being named, the

    language of names takes leave of itself, of its nominal character, not by actually

    becoming something else but by naming the structural potentiality of such leave-

    taking. In short, as medium, language parts with itself and can thus be said to

    constitutea medium of virtuality, avirtual medium that cannot bemeasuredby the

    possibilityof self-fulfilmentbut by its constitutive alterability, Weber, Benjamins

    Abilities, 42. Both Hamacher and Weber relate therefore language to the title of the

    second of the two sections which, according to a letter Benjamin sent to Scholem in

    December 1920, would have composed the second part of his Politik: teleologywithout final purpose [Teleologie ohne Endzweck] (cf.GB 2:109). This, Weber adds,

    only insofar as the word without defines a relation not of simple exclusion or

    negation, but of participation with the out-side of an irreducible and yet

    constitutive exteriority, Weber, Benjamins Abilities, 197.73 Der Name ist dasjenige, durchdas sich nichts mehr, und in dem die Sprache selbst

    undabsolutsichmitteilt. ImNamenist dasgeistige Wesen,das sich mitteilt, die Sprache.74 Das Wort soll etwas mitteilen (auer sich selbst).75 in den Abgrund der Mittelbarkeit aller Mitteilung, des Wortes als Mittel, des eitlen

    Wortes verfiel, in den Abgrund des Geschwatzes.76 Der Baum der Erkenntnis stand nicht wegen der Aufschlu sse uber Gut und Bose, die

    er zu geben vermocht hatte, im Garten Gottes, sondern als Wahrzeichen des Gerichts

    uber den Fragenden. Diese ungeheure Ironie ist das Kennzeichen des mythischen

    Ursprung des Rechts.77 Cf. Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, 1144.78 weil die zum Kompromi fuhrende Strebung nicht von sich aus, sondern von auen,

    eben von der Gegenstrebung, motiviert wird, weil aus jedem Kompromi, wie freiwillig

    auch immer aufgenommen, der Zwangscharakter nicht weggedacht werden kann.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447 443

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    7/10

    of a superordinate end: compromise is a form of law-positing

    which has no law-preserving violence at disposition.79The work of

    diplomats lacks this law-positing character because it is beyond all

    legal systems and therefore beyond violence80 (GS2.1:195/SW

    1:247). In Unterredung, finally, language as medium is not

    determined von auen, from outside, but rather it wraps

    and involves, in a way, the speaker; it is the speaker

    who is referred to by language, and not the other way round,

    and it is this objectiveness of language which constitutes it as

    techne.81 When Beatrice Hanssen writes thus that in Unterredung

    Benjamin seemingly retained the legacy of liberalism, she misses

    the mark.82

    The notion of language as pure means relates to another

    fundamental notion: pure language. In the language essay

    Benjamin states that language itself constitutes the mental being

    of man, who therefore cannot communicate himself by it, but onlyin it:

    The quintessence of this intensive totality of language as the

    mental being of man is the name. Man is the namer; by this we

    recognize that through him pure language speaks.83 (GS

    2.1:144/SW1:65)

    Pure language is identified here with the name-language:

    language, and in it a mental entity, only expresses itself purely

    where it speaks in name84 (GS2.1:145/SW1:65). This language as

    the paradisiacal language [paradiesische Sprache] is one of perfect

    knowledge (GS2.1:144/SW1:71).In the 1921 translation essay this

    notion takes a slightly different connotation: pure language is here

    defined as the totality of their [all human languages] intentions

    supplementing one another85 (GS4.1:13/SW1:257). The kinship

    [Verwandtschaft] of languages resides in the fact that what is

    meant [das Gemeinte] in all of them is the same; they only differ in

    the way of meaning [die Art des Meinens]. Das Gemeinte is in a

    constant state of flux [Wandel] an historical flux which

    translation helps developing by transposing each time the

    language of the original into a higher and purer linguistic air86

    until it is able to emerge as the pure language from the harmony

    of all the various ways of meaning.87 Pure language corresponds

    therefore to the messianic end of the history of all historical

    languages, a final, conclusive, decisive stage of all linguistic

    creation88 (GS4.1:14/SW 1:257), a tensionless and even silent

    depository of the ultimate secrets forwhich all thoughtstrives, the

    language of truth or the true language89 (GS4.1:16/SW1:259). It

    is at the same time present, as a nucleus [Kern], albeit hidden and

    fragmentary, in the life and transformation of historical languages,

    and thus also stands, Hanssen argues, simultaneously in a relation

    of immanence and transcendence to empirical languages.90

    Language, therefore, pure insofar as beyond its utilitarian and

    symbolic functions, that which is purely language, nothing but

    language.91 Neither a Ursprache nor a universal language, pure

    language signifies the messianic end (telos and not Zweck) of the

    historical movement of all languages, a teleological movement

    (but an intentionless one,92 without final purposes, ohne End-

    zwecke) of progressive purification towards a sort of cumulative

    totality which constitutes nevertheless the empty space of

    universal linguisticity.93

    Hamacher interestingly relates the notion of pure language to

    Benjamins critique of Kant: what in the1918 Kants essay Benjamin

    called pure epistemological (transcendental) consciousness

    [reinen erkenntnis-theoretischen (transzendentalen) Bewusstsein]

    (GS2.1:162/SW1:104),for which he advocated against subjectivism

    and the consequent subject-object divide, could also be called,

    Hamacherargues,a theoryof a puretranscendental language.In thesame way that the pure transcendental consciousness would

    overcome the relation between subjects and objects, pure language

    overcomes that between languages and subjects, or languages and

    objects, and refers rather to relations internal to languages and

    between languages, to relations of communication [Mitteilbarkeit],

    translation, linguisticality [Sprachlichkeit], in a word, to the medial

    character of language and thus to its Wesen.94 However, Hamacher

    also underlines an important commonality with Kant, especially in

    the notion of translatability: because it structurally transcends the

    limits of finite subjectivity, and is as such a possibility that does not

    need to refer to any actual reality, translatability presents the

    character of a demand [Forderung] analogous to the Kantian moral

    law. Like the moral law, translatability is not moulded on the

    conditions of its fulfilment, but is a demand which arises from theessence [Wesen] of each work, and thus from language itself.95 A

    similar point is made by Figal when he argues that Benjamin is still

    strongly Kantian in his systematic determination of the morality in

    language on its intensive totality.96 We could stretchthe argument

    to argue that the tension on which pure language is construed (like

    the politics of pure means, and finally also pure violence) still

    presents a strong affinity with Kants formulation of the moral act.

    Pure language is related to another fundamental notion: the

    expressionless [das Ausdruckslose]. In the language essay the

    79 Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 189.80 jenseits aller Rechtsordnung und also Gewalt.81 Cf. A. Hirsch, Gewalt jenseits der Gewalt: Zu Walter Benjamins Theorie der

    Gewaltlosigkeit, nebst einigen Anmerkungen zu einer Kritik der Reprsa ntation,

    Etudes Germaniques, 51.1 (JanuaryMarch 1996), 22.82 Cf. Hanssen, Critique of Violence, 22.83 Der Inbegriff dieser intensiven Totalitat der Sprache als des geistigen Wesen des

    Menschen istder Name.Der Menschist derNennende, daranerkennenwir, dass ausihm

    die reine Sprache spricht.84 Die Sprache und inihr ein geistiges Wesen spricht sich nur da rein aus, wo sie im

    Namen spricht.85

    die Allheit ihrer einander erganzenden Intentionen.86 in einen gleichsam hoheren und reineren Luftkreis der Sprache hinauf.87 bis es aus der Harmonie all jener Arten des Meinens als die reine Sprache

    herauszutreten vermag.88 ein letztes, endgultiges und entscheidendes Stadium aller Sprachfugung.89 Wenn anders es aber eine Sprache der Wahrheit gibt, in welcher die letzten

    Geheimnisse, um die alles Denken sich muht, spannungslos und selbst schweigend

    aufbewahrt sind, so ist diese Sprache der Wahrheit die wahre Sprache90 Pure language, then, as the movement of language, was immanent to the

    diversity of empirical languages, yet it transcended them. At the risk of pressuring

    the limits of the German language, one could perhaps say that in Benjamins essay

    the German term for translation (Ubersetzung) no longer only denoted transfer or

    transposition, as it does etymologically, but also pointed to a transcendence, to a

    law (Gesetz) that transcends, that is uber, above. Inasmuch as this transcendence

    manifested itself in translation, it was also at once immanent. As such, its ur-image

    (Urbild) was the interlinear version of the scriptures. Pure language as translation

    was that which inhabited and exceeded singular languages and idioms, Hanssen,

    Walter Benjamins Other History, 35.

    91 Cf. Gasche, Saturnine Vision and the Question of Difference, 92, and C. Jacobs,

    The Monstrosity of Translation, MLN90 (1975), 7601.92 Cf. T. Dorr, Kritik und Ubersetzung: Die Praxis der Reproduktion im Fruhwerk

    Walter Benjamins (Gieen, 1988), 11920, and A. Hirsch, Die Aufgabe DesUbersetzers,Benjamin-Handbuch, 614.93 Cf. V. Vitiello, Il linguaggio: Benjamin e Heidegger a confronto,Aut Aut: Rivista

    di Filosofia e Cultura, 2734 (MayAugust 1996), 110. Samuel Weber writes:

    language that is pure of everything that is outside it is a language that would

    consist of pure signifying, something that is aporetical, to be sure, since signifying

    always entails a signified and hence cannot be entirely pure. But a relation to

    language in which syntax the sequential arrangement of words takes

    precedence over the time-and-space transcending rues of grammar and semantics;

    in which the ways of meaning, their distribution and relations, have priority over

    what is meant this would be a language that seems to approach what Benjamin

    means by pure language. This would be a language that performs by signifying

    without being absorbed or determined by entities that appear to exist

    independently of all signifying, Weber, Benjamins Abilities, 745.94 W. Hamacher, Intensive Sprachen,Ubersetzen: Walter Benjamin, ed. Christiaan

    L. Hart Nibbrig (Frankfurt a.M, 2001), 1756.95 Hamacher, Intensive Sprachen, 180.96

    Figal, Die Ethik Walter Benjamins als Philosophie der reinen Mittel, 15.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447444

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    8/10

    question of the inexpressible and the inexpressed [das Unauspre-

    chliches, das Unausgesprochene] is connected to the concept of

    revelation [Offenbarung]: revelation is thelinguisticstate where the

    most expressed is at thesame time thepurelymental97 (GS2.1:146/

    SW 1:67). This does not entail, however, a pure correspondence

    between language and communication: For language is in every

    case not only communication of the communicable but also, at the

    same time, a symbol of the noncommunicable98 (GS 2.1:156/SW

    1:74). This thought is developed in the translationessay precisely in

    relation to pure language:

    In this pure language which no longer means or expresses

    anythingbut is, as expressionlessand creative Word, thatwhich

    is meant in all languages all information, all sense, and all

    intention finally encounter a stratum in which theyare destined

    to be extinguished.99 (GS4.1:19/SW1:261)

    Weber points out that pure language is essentially described

    negatively, as meaning-less, intention-less and expression-less.100

    It is the messianic, transcendent telos in which all languages are

    destined to be extinguished and this will be a fundamental point

    for the analysis of pure violence. At the same time, however, it is

    also the immanent unexpressed and inexpressible which inhabitsall historical languages and as such disarranges and interrupts the

    continuum of signification. On this aspect Benjamin will found the

    power of critique.

    Critical violence

    The years which separate the language essay and the translation

    essay saw Benjamins intense engagement with Kants work, an

    engagement which became critical counterposition and led him to

    attempt a peculiarAufhebungof theKantian critical project along the

    lines of the philosophy of language exposed in the language essay,

    combined with the criticism of art he found in the Early German

    Romantics.101 The critical model elaborated in these crucial years

    will remain a constant in Benjamins later work and will be appliedto the most diverse fields, from literature to history to politics; the

    cornerstones of this critical project are represented by the essay on

    Goethes Elective Affinities and the book onthe German Baroque Play

    of Mourning [Ursprung des deutschen Trauerspiels, written between

    May 1924 and April 1925]. The former recasts pure language in the

    aestheticfield as theexpressionless[das Ausdruckslose].Theworkof

    art, Benjamin writes, as form enchants chaos momentarily into the

    world102andbecomes mere semblance[bloer Schein]intheforms

    of mere beauty and mere harmony [bloe Schonheit and bloe

    Harmonie] (GS 1.1:181/SW1:340). Semblance, Winfried Mennin-

    ghaus notes, endows beauty with the main trait of myth: ambiguity

    [Zweideutigkeit] (GS 1.1:175/SW 1:335).103 What arrests this

    semblance and interrupts the harmony is the expressionless: it

    compels the trembling harmony to stop and through its objection

    immortalises its quivering.104 Benjamin defines the expressionless

    as critical violence [kritische Gewalt] insofar as it possesses violence

    asa moraldictum [moralisches Wort]: it is only the moral word that

    can dispel the ambiguity of semblance and introduce what is

    presentedas thecharacteristicof truth andjustice: unequivocalness

    [Eindeutigkeit] (GS1.1:162,174/SW1:326,335).105 This moral word

    appears as sublime violence:

    In the expressionless, the sublime violence of the true appears

    as that which determines the language of the real world

    according to the laws of the moral world. For it shatters

    whatever still survives as the legacy of chaos in all beautiful

    semblance: the false,errant totality the absolute totality. Only

    the expressionless completes the work, by shattering it into a

    thing of shards, into a fragment of the true world, into the torsoof a symbol.106 (GS1.1:181/SW1:340)107

    A passage from HolderlinsAnmerkungen zum Odipus [Annota-

    tions to Oedipus] helps Benjamin clarify the concept: the

    expressionless emerges in the Holderlin quotation as the caesura,

    the pure word, the counter-rhythmic rupture,108 in which, along

    with harmony, every expression simultaneously comes to a

    standstill, in order to give free reign to an expressionless power

    inside all artistic media109 (GS 1.1:1812/SW 1:3401). The

    expressionless shatters [zerschlagt], destroys and reduces

    semblance that semblance which is the aesthetic correlate of

    myth to shardsand fragments. The violent caesura constitutedby

    the pure word entails a moral force; or, better, the violence which

    constitutes the moral word is caesura, rupture, insofar as it

    introduces the unequivocalness of truth and justice purity into

    the ambiguity of appearance and myth. This moral word,

    Burkhardt Lindner writes, is no word and entails no signification;

    rather, it is interruption of the mythical unity of expression,

    semblance and signification.110 Or, as Hamacher famously argued,

    the purity of this expressionless violence pure word as

    immanent pure language, that which remains unexpressed and

    inexpressible is never positing, forming, or transforming, but

    afformative. As objection [Einspruch], it is not itself a word, not a

    97 das Ausgesprochenste zugleich das reine Geistige ist.98 Es ist namlich Sprache in jedem Falle nicht allein Mitteilung des Mitteilbaren,

    sondern zugleich Symbol des Nicht-Mitteilbaren.99 In dieser reinen Sprache, die nichts mehr meint und nichts mehr ausdruckt, sondern

    als ausdrucksloses und schopferisches Wort das in allen Sprachen Gemeinte ist, trifft

    endlich alle Mitteilung, aller Sinn und alle Intention auf eine Schicht, in der sie zu

    erloschen bestimmt sind.100 Weber,Benjamins Abilities, 77.101 Benjamins correspondence helps outlining this development: if in October

    1917he still harbouredthe idea of writing hisdoctoraldissertationat theuniversityof Berne on Kant and history (GB 1:3901), when he finally read Kants relevant

    works on thesubject,namely Idee zu einerallgemeinen Geschichtein weltburgerlicher

    Absicht[ Idea For a Universal History with a Cosmopolitan Purpose, 1784] andZum

    ewigen Frieden[Perpetual Peace, 1795], he was strongly disappointed. In December

    of the same year he wrote to Scholem: The issue in Kant is not much history but

    certain historical constellations of ethical interest. In addition, precisely the ethical

    side of history as specific observation is made inaccessible and the postulate of an

    analytical mode proper to the natural sciences is established [Es handelt sich bei

    Kant weniger um die Geschichte als um gewisse geschichtliche Konstellationen von

    ethischem Interesse. Und noch dazu wird gerade die ethische Seite der Geschichte als

    einer besondern Betrachtung unzuganglich hingestellt und das Postulat einer

    naturwissenschaftlichen Betrachtungsweise und Methode aufgestellt] (GB 1:408). He

    maintains the necessity of an engagement with the letterof Kants philosophy (GB

    1:4023) and considers and later discards the hypothesis of a doctoral

    dissertation on the Kantian notion of unendliche Aufgabe (infinite task). Kant

    remains the fundamental reference,but as thegreat opponent[dergrote Gegener],

    as Benjamin writes in a letter to Ernst Schoen in May 1918 (GB 1:4556).

    102 verzaubert (Chaos) auf einen Augenblick zur Welt.103 W. Menninghaus, Das Ausdruckslose: Walter Benjamins Metamorphosen der

    Bilderlosigkeit,Fur Walter Benjamin: Dokumente, Essays und ein Entwurf, ed. Ingrid

    und Konrad Scheurmann (Frankfurt a.M., 1992), 175.104 zwingt das Ausdruckslose die zitternde Harmonie einzuhalten und verewigt durch

    seinen Einspruch ihr Beben.105 Cf. Menninghaus, Das Ausdruckslose, 175. There is no truth, for there is no

    unequivocalness andhence no error in myth[Es gibt keine Wahrheit,dennes gibt

    keine Eindeutigkeit und also nicht einmal Irrtum im Mythos] ( GS1.1:162/SW1:326).106 Im Ausdruckslosen erscheint die erhabne Gewalt des Wahren, wie es nach Gesetzen

    der moralischen Welt die Sprache der wirklichen bestimmt. Dieses namlich zerschlagt

    was in allem schonen Schein als die Erbschaft des Chaos noch uberdauert: die falsche,

    irrende Totalitat die absolute. Dieses erst vollendet das Werk, welches es zum

    Stuckwerk zerschlagt, zum Fragmente der wahren Welt, zum Torso eines Symbols.107 This page is taken almost literarily from an early fragment written in 1919

    1920, On Semblance [Uber Schein]. Cf. GS 1.3:8323/SW 1:2245.108 Casur (...), das reine Wort, die gegenrhythmische Unterbrechung.109 jeder Ausdruck sich legt, um einer innerhalb aller Kunstmittel ausdruckslosen

    Gewalt Raum zu geben.110 B. Lindner, Goethes Wahlverwandtschaften. Goethe im Gesamtwerk,

    Benjamin-Handbuch, 48990.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447 445

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    9/10

    positing, but the interruption of propositional utterance by

    something which neither speaks nor posits; pure, wordless

    word, it does not belong to any spoken language, but, as pure

    language, it constitutes the very possibility of language and social

    life themselves.111 It is perceptible in tragedy as the falling silent

    of the hero [als Verstummen des Helden] (GS1.1:182/SW1:341).112

    The sublimity of the true word constitutes the secret

    [Geheimnis] at the core of the critique of beauty: the expressionless,

    though contrasting with the semblance, stands in a necessary

    relationship to it, and this makes for the unity of veil and veiled

    which constitutes beauty (GS1.1:1956/SW 1:3501). As it has

    been noted, Kantian suggestions are here very strong, and they are

    acknowledged by Benjamin himself.113 As Uwe Steiner writes,

    Kants third critique is here revisited along the lines of Benjamins

    philosophy of language, whereby the dialectics between expres-

    sionless and revelation takes on the traits of the third moment of

    the Analytic of the Beautiful: the purposiveness without any

    purpose [Zweckmaigkeit ohne allen Zweck]114 (KU, B 62 = A 61/

    54), which for Kant expresses the agreement of the form with the

    subjective harmony of imagination and understanding, becomes

    the main trait of revelation [Offenbarung] as sublime disclosure

    [Enthullung].115 The expressionless, then, presents evident traits of

    the Analyticof theSublime, especially in itsnegative character (cf.

    KU, B 118 = A 116/81), which Kant explicitly relates to the JewishBilderverbot, and in its symbolic analogy to morality in us (cf.KU, B

    125 = A 123/86).116 More generally, Menninghaus points out, das

    Ausdruckslose explicitly resonates with a number of aesthetic-

    theological concepts which sustain Kants project and all end with

    the syllable-los [-less]: zwecklos [purposeless], interesselos [disin-

    terested], begriffslos [non-conceptual] and more importantly

    bilderlos, in the form of the JewishBilderverbot, of which it would

    play a series of variation.117 As in Kant, and strongly influence by

    his work, purity stands in Benjamin as some form of sublime losigkeitat the core of his philosophical project.

    Pure violence

    Hamacher famously related the critical violence of the

    expressionless of the Goethe essay to the pure violence of

    Critique of Violence. Using the terminology of speech-act theory,

    he called afformative the deposing [Entsetzung] which charac-

    terises pure violence, since, like the expressionless, it does not

    perform any signification or positing [Setzung], but rather

    interrupts it. As such, pure violence is non-violent and non-

    instrumental and may at any time if not universally at anytime

    break through the cycle of laws and their decay.118

    The notion of pure violence arises as a response to the quest for

    a different kind of violence [. . .] that certainly could be either the

    justified or the unjustified means to [just] ends but was not related

    to them as means at all but in some different way 119 (GS2.1:196/SW1:247). It is the ultimate task of a politics of pure means to

    identify such pure, immediate violence [reinen unmittelbaren

    Gewalt] that might call a halt to the mythic violence of law. The

    language Benjamin uses to describe this pure violence became

    suspicious to many readers, notably to Derrida,who sawit haunted

    by the spectre of radical destruction120: Benjamin speaks of

    destruction or annihilation [Vernichtung] of legal violence/power

    and describes pure violence non only as divine [gottliche Gewalt],

    but as law-destroying [rechtsvernichtend], striking [schlagend],

    lethal without bloodshed [auf unblutige Weise letal] and as not

    stopping short of annihilation [macht nicht Halt vor der Vernich-

    tung] (GS 2.1:199/SW 1:24950); moreover, this revolutionary

    violence [revolutionare Gewalt] is also said to possibly manifest

    itself in a true war and in the crowds divine judgement on acriminal121 and is not recognizable as such with certainty. Slavoj

    Zizek conceives it thus as divine in the sense of the Latin motto vox

    populi, vox dei, pure, revolutionary outburst of violence which

    strikes out ofnowhere and has noend in sight.122 The last sentence

    of theessay describes itas thesignandsealbut never the means of

    sacred dispatch123 and calls itdie waltende, translated by Edmund

    Jephcott as the sovereign (GS2.1:2023/SW1:252). It is no means,

    and in this sense has no meaning: like language as medium, it does

    non signify anything, it is a pure sign.

    The difficulty in interpreting this figure has led to the most

    diverse reading. Vittoria Borsospeaks of an ambivalence of both

    pure violence and pure language, but this is a dangerous term,

    because it resonates with that ambiguity [Zweideutigkeit] which

    rather characterises, for Benjamin, law and myth.124

    It is importantthus to clarify this point. Giorgio Agamben importantly calls the

    attention to a letter Benjamin wrote to Ernst Schoen on 29 January

    111 Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, 11534.112 The theme of silence can be traced back to Benjamins early writings at the

    time of his involvement in the Jugendbewegung. In The Conversation [Das

    Gesprach], thefirstpartof the1913 unpublished Metaphysicsof Youth[Metaphysik

    der Jugend], Benjamin writes that conversation strives toward silence [Das

    Gesprach strebt zum Schweigen]; in silence, the listener holds true language [die

    wahreSprache] in readinessand leads the conversationto theedge of language,and

    the speaker creates the silence of a new language, he, its first auditor [der Horend e

    fuhrte das Gesprach zum Rande der Sprache und der Sprachende erschuf das Schweigen

    einer neuen Sprache, er, ihr erster Lauscher]. Silence is the internal frontier of

    conversation and greatnessis the eternal silence afterthe conversation [Schweigen

    ist die innere Grenze des Gespraches a nd Groe ist das ewige Schweigen nach dem

    Gesprach] (GS2.1:913/SW1:67). This theme traverses, as a subterranean current,the following writings on language and aesthetics and finally re-emerges in the

    Goethe essay and, more powerfully, in the Trauerspiel book. Here tragic silence as

    speachlessness [Sprachlosigkeit] intensifies the condition of the tragic hero;

    Benjamin quotes from Rosenzweigs Stern der Erlosung[Star of Redemption, 1921]:

    the tragicherohas only onelanguagethatis completely properto him: silence[ Der

    tragische Held hat nur eine Sprache, die ihm vollkommen entspricht: eben das

    Schweigen] (GS 1.1:286/OT 108). Silence represents the sublimity of linguistic

    expression [einer Erfahrung vom Erhabnen des Sprachlichen Ausdrucks ] (GS1.1:288/

    OT109). As Menninghaus notes, it is precisely the absence of words that represents

    the maximum of communication [Mitteilung]: it is an articulation of the non-

    articulation. But more importantly, this silence is sublime [erhabne], like the

    violence of truth which appears in the expressionless. Cf. Menninghaus, Das

    Ausdruckslose, 174.113 Kants doctrine, that the foundation of beauty is a relational character,

    accordingly carries through victoriously, in a much higher sphere than the

    psychological, its methodical tendencies. Like revelation, all beauty holds in itself

    the orders of the history of philosophy. For beauty makes visible not the idea butrather the latters secret [Kants Lehre, dass ein Relationscharakter die Grundlage der

    Schonheit sei, setzt demnach in einer sehr viel hohern Sphare als der psychologischen

    siegreich ihre methodischen Tendenzen durch. Alle Schonheit halt wie die Offenbarung

    geschichtsphilosophische Ordnungen in sich. Denn sie macht nicht die Idee sichtbar,

    sondern deren Geheimnis] (GS 1.1:1956/SW1:351).114 Schonheit ist Form der Zweckmaigkeit eines Gegenstandes, sofern sie, ohne

    Vorstellung eines Zwecks, an ihm wahrgenommen wird.115 U. Steiner, Kritik,Benjamins Begriffe, ed. Michael Opitz and Edmut Wizisla, vol.

    2 (Frankfurt a.M., 2000), 509.116 Perhaps there is no sublimer passage in the Jewish Law than the command,

    Thou shaltnot make to thyself anygraven image,nor thelikenessof anythingwhichis in

    heaven or on the earth or under the earth, etc. [. . .] The same is true of the moral law

    and of the tendency to morality in us [Vielleicht gibt es keine erhabenere Stelle im

    Gesetzbuche der Juden, als das Gebot: Du sollst dir kein Bildnis machen, noch irgend ein

    Gleichnis, weder dessen was im Himmel, noch aud der Erden, noch unter der Erden ist

    u.s.w. (...) Eben dasselbe gilt auch von der Vorstellung des moralischen Gesetzes und der

    Anlage zur Moralitat in uns] (KU, B 125=A 123/86). Cf. Steiner, Kritik, 508.

    117 Menninghaus, Das Ausdruckslose, 170.118 Hamacher, Afformative, Strike, 11389.119 eine Gewalt anderer Art[...], die dannfreilichzu jenenZweckennicht dasberechtigte

    noch das unberechtigte Mittel sein konnte, sondern uberhaupt nicht als Mittel zu ihnen,

    vielmehr irgendwie anders, sich verhalten wurde.120 Cf. J. Derrida, Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority, Cardozo

    Law Review 11 (19891990), especially the Post-scriptum, 11405.121 im wahren Kriegeand im Gottesgericht der Menge am Verbrecher.122 Cf. S. Zizek,Violence (New York, 2008), 178205.123 Insignium und Siegel, niemals Mittel heiliger Vollstreckung.124 Cf. V. Borso, Walter Benjamin - Theologe und Politiker: eine gefahrliche

    Verbindung,Theologie und Politik: Walter Benjamin und ein Paradigma der Moderne ,

    ed. Bernd Witte and Mauro Ponzi (Berlin, 2005), 645.

    C. Salzani/ History of European Ideas 36 (2010) 438447446

  • 7/24/2019 Purity Benjamin Kant

    10/10

    1919 and in which he gives a definition of purity. Benjamin

    writes:

    The purity of a being is neverunconditional, or absolute; it is

    always subjected to a condition. This condition varies depend-

    ing on the being the purity of which is at issue; however, this

    condition is neverto be found in the being itself. In other words,

    the purity of any (finite) being does not depend on itself.125 (GB

    2:112, emphases in the original)

    Agamben calls this conception of purity relational rather than

    substantial and argues therefore that the purity of pure violence is

    not a substantial characteristic belonging to the violent action in

    itself; in other words, the difference between pure violence and

    mythico-juridical violence does not lie in the violence itself, but in

    itsrelationto somethingexternal, that is,in itsrelationto law. This

    relation, however,cannot be that of meansand end, but only that of

    the medialityof thepuremedium identified in thelanguageessays.

    In fact, like many other interpreters, Agamben underlines the

    relation between pure violence and pure language: pure violence

    is that which does not stand in a relation of means toward an end,

    but holds itself in relation to its own mediality. As such, he argues,

    pure violence is finally attested to only as the exposure anddeposition of the relation between violence and law.126 Pure

    violence, he concludes, exposes and severs the nexus between law

    and violence and can thus appear in the end not as violence that

    governs or executes (die schaltende) butas violence that purelyacts

    and manifests (die waltende).127 The expression purely acts

    [puramente agisce] needs though a specification: acts cannot be

    read performatively, as Hamacher would say, but as the

    afformative interruption of the expressionless pure language.

    Samuel Weber acutely notes, however, that, if purity is not a

    substantial but a relational notion, then how can it consist in an

    action that manifests violence itself or as such, as distinct from

    everything other than itself? Or, he continues, is there a kind of

    manifestation, a kind of act that is defined precisely through just

    such a relation to something other than itself? What, in short, is

    involved in a violence that is waltend but not schaltend? Can the

    twobe as clearly separatedor distinguished as Agamben, following

    Benjamin, seems to believe?128 Weber might have in mind the

    peculiar utilisation of the verb walten in German: used alone, it can

    mean to rule, as inthe expressionuber jemanden oder etwas walten

    (to rule over somebody or something); it is however used often in

    combination with the verb lassen (to let, allow, make), as in the

    expressions Vernunft walten lassen (to let reason prevail),

    Vorsicht/Milde walten lassen (to exercise caution/leniency), Gnade

    walten lassen (to show mercy), jemanden walten lassen (to let

    somebody have a free rein, to let somebody do as he pleases); as

    noun, it is used in expressions like das Walten der Naturgewalten/

    Gottes (the workings of the forces of nature/of God), and the

    expression das walte Gott means simply amen, so be it. It is

    interesting to note that walten is commonly used in combination

    withschaltenin the idiomatic expression schalten und walten (to

    bustle around) andfrei schalten und walten (to do what one wants,

    to have a free hand). The common usage, we could argue, testifies

    of the intimate relation of the two terms, precisely that relation

    which is at issue in the purification of violence.

    The perspective that must be adopted in finally assessing the

    purity of violence is that invoked by Benjamin at the beginning of

    the last paragraph of the essay:

    The critique of violence is the philosophy of its history the

    philosophy of this history because only the idea of its

    development makes possible a critical, discriminating, and

    decisive approach to its temporal data.129 (GS 2.1:202/SW

    1:251)

    The pivotal term is here Ausgang, which Jephcott renders as

    development, but which could also be translated as outcome,

    exit, egress,or, in relation to a story or to history (both Geschichtein German), as denouement or conclusion. The idea of thisAusgangis to be read neither as a Kantian regulative idea nor as

    the idea of the Platonic tradition, but rather as the idea as

    constellation of the Trauerspiel book, intimately related to the

    notion of Ursprung, origin.130 Ursprung and Ausgang, in their

    correlation, define the philosophy of history which informs and

    connects both Critique of Violence and The Task of the

    Translator.We can, therefore, recur again to theanalogy with pure

    language: pure violence can be described as the messianic,

    transcendent telosin which, like pure language at the end of the

    history of languages, the connection betweenschaltenandwalten,

    and thus the mythic bound which unites law and violence, is

    destined to be extinguished. It is important, though, not to forget

    also the immanent side of pure language: at the same time, we

    must read pure violence as the immanent critical violence that, like

    the expressionless within every linguistic expression, disarranges

    and thus exposes the continuum of this connection; as pure

    language constitutes the potency of language as dunamis, insofar as

    it interrupts and dissolves the signification of every historical

    language, so pure violence constitutes the dunamis of the

    deposition of the schalten-walten connection and thus the

    messianic idea of a new historical epoch [ein neues geschichtliches

    Zeitalter] (GS2.1:202/SW1:252).

    125 Die Reinheit eines Wesens istniemals unbedingt, oder absolut, sie ist stets einer

    Bedingung unterworfen. Diese Bedingung ist verschieden je nach dem Wesen um dessen

    Reinheit es sich handelt; niemalsaber liegt diese Bedingung in dem Wesen selbst. Mit

    anderen Worten: Die Reinheit jedes(endlichen) Wesenist nichtvon ihmselbst abhangig.126 G. Agamben,State of Exception, trans. Kevin Attell (Chicago and London, 2005),

    612. Axel Honneth seems to mean something similar when he writes that its

    function is to prepare the terminology with which Benjamin will asses the relation

    be