ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

  • Upload
    paavofi

  • View
    215

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    1/7

    The 4th International Conference on Cognitive Neurodynamics ICCN2013VERY ROUGH DRAFT (2013-10-24) , PLEASE DO NOT CIRCULATE

    Weak vs. strong quantum cognition

    Paavo Pylkknen

    Department of Cognitive Neuroscience and Philosophy, University of Skvde,

    P.O. Box 408, SE-541 28 Skvde, Sweden andDepartment of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies, P.O. Box 24, FI-

    00014 University of Helsinki, Finland.

    e-mail:[email protected]

    Abstract In recent decades some cognitive scientists have adopted a program ofquantum cognition. For example, Pothos and Busemeyer (PB) argue that there are

    empirical results concerning human decision-making and judgment that can beelegantly accounted for by quantum probability (QP) theory, while classical

    (Bayesian) probability (CP) theory fails. They suggest that the reason why

    quantum probability works better is because some cognitive phenomena are

    analogous to quantum phenomena. This naturally gives rise to a further question

    about why they are analogous. Is this a pure coincidence, or is there a deeper

    reason? For example, could the neural processes underlying cognition involvesubtle quantum effects, thus explainingwhy cognition obeys QP? PB are agnostic

    about this controversial issue, and thus their kind of program could be labeled asweak quantum cognition (analogously to the program of weak artificial

    intelligence as characterized by Searle). However, there is a long tradition of

    speculating about the role of subtle quantum effects in the neural correlates ofcognition, constituting a program of strong quantum cognition or quantumcognitive neuroscience. In this paper I will be considering the prospects of

    strong quantum cognition, by briefly reviewing and commenting on some of thekey proposals.

    Keywords

    Quantum cognition, quantum probability, analogy

    1. Introduction

    In their recent Behavioral and Brain Science target article Can quantumprobability provide a new direction for cognitive modeling? Emmanuel Pothos

    and Jerome Busemeyer (PB) (2013) make a convincing case that there are

    empirical results concerning human decision making and judgment that can be

    elegantly accounted for by quantum probability (QP) theory, while classical

    (Bayesian) probability (CP) theory fails. In particular, they point out that human

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]:[email protected]
  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    2/7

    2

    judgment and preference often display order and context effects, violations of the

    law of total probability and failures of compositionality, and that in such cases QP

    - with features such as superposition and entanglement - provides a natural

    explanation of cognitive process. More generally, they suggest that QP is

    potentially relevant in any behavioral situation that involves uncertainty.

    Such success in modeling raises the question of how can it be that QP

    which was developed to account for quantum physical phenomena could possibly

    be able to account for cognitive phenomena. PB do not discuss this issue at great

    length, but suggest that the reason is because some cognitive phenomena are

    analogous to quantum phenomena. But this gives rise to a further question: why

    are these phenomena analogous to each other? Is it a mere coincidence or is there

    some deeper explanation? For example, might the neural processes underlying

    cognition be quantum-like in some way? PB remain agnostic about thiscontroversial issue, and thus we might call their program an instance of weak

    quantum cognition (somewhat analogously to the program of weak AI in

    artificial intelligence research; cf. also the program of weak quantum theory,

    where one applies some, but not all formal features of quantum theory to explain

    cognitive phenomena, see Atmaspacher et al. 2002). However, there is a long

    tradition of speculating about the role of subtle quantum effects in the neural

    correlates of cognition, constituting a program of strong quantum cognition or

    quantum cognitive neuroscience. While it may be a good research strategy in

    cognitive science to pursue weak quantum cognition without worrying about the

    underlying reasons for why QP works for cognition, it would clearly be a major

    scientific breakthrough is strong quantum cognition would turn out to be correct.

    It is thus worth giving attention to the current state-of-the-art in strong quantumcognition. The aim of this paper is to briefly review and comment some major

    developments.

    2. Strong quantum cognition: subtle quantum effects in the neural correlates

    of cognition?

    There are various ways in which the neural processes underlying cognition could

    be quantum-like. The strongest possibility is that they literally involve subtle

    quantum effects. For example, following Niels Bohr, David Bohm speculated

    about this possibility already in 1951 in his textbookQuantum theory.

    Anticipating the current research on quantum cognition, he drew attention to what

    he considered to be remarkable point-by-point analogies between quantum

    processes and thought. He added that it would provide a natural explanation of

    these analogies if it turned out that some key neural processes (e.g. in synapses)

    were subject to quantum-theoretical limitations (for a discussion of Bohms

    analogies see

    Pylkknen 2004).

    Harald Atmanspacher (2011) has provided a useful overview of various

    programs of what I have above call strong quantum cognition. First of all, there

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    3/7

    3

    are approaches that stay within the usual interpretation of the quantum theory.

    There is the von Neumann-Wigner line of thought that assumes that consciousness

    plays a role in quantum state reductions; in Stapps later development of this

    approach the neural correlates of conscious intentional acts are assumed to involve

    quantum state reductions. There is the Ricciardi-Umezawa-Vitiello approach that

    sees mental states, particularly memory states, as vacuum states of quantum fields

    (this approach has been given an imaginative philosophical interpretation by

    Globus 2003). Finally, there is the Beck-Eccles approach, where it is assumed

    that due to quantum mechanical processes the frequency of exocytosis at a

    synaptic cleft can be controlled by mental intentions, without violating the

    conservation of energy (for a discussion of this last approach see also Hiley and

    Pylkknen 2005).

    Atmanspacher also draws attention to programs of strong quantumcognition that involve further extensions or generalizations of present-day

    quantum theory. Most notably, there is Penroses proposal that human (say

    mathematical) insight is non-computable and that the physiological correlates of

    such insight thus need to involve non-computable physical processes. He thinks

    that such process might well be related to quantum state reduction. However,

    Penrose is not satisfied with quantum state reduction as this is characterized in the

    usual interpretation of quantum theory. Instead, he proposes that gravity brings

    about the reduction under certain circumstances, which allows the possibility of an

    orchestrated objective reduction (ORCH-OR) the idea being that the reduction

    can take place without the activity of a human conscious observer, and in an

    orchestrated way. This involves an extension of current quantum theory, in which

    latter the state reductions obey the usual laws of quantum probability. Togetherwith Hameroff, Penrose proposed that neural microtubules might provide a site

    where ORCH-ORs could take place. Their assumption is that ORCH-ORs in

    neural microtubules constitute conscious moments. The idea is similar to Stapps

    later ideas, but one difference is that while Stapp stays within the usual

    interpretation of quantum theory, Penroses approach involves going beyond it (in

    that the reductions can be objective and orchestrated, and need not obey the usual

    quantum laws).

    Those who advocate strong quantum cognition typically encounter the

    criticism that quantum effects are washed out in the warm, wet and noisy

    conditions of the macroscopic world and brains in particular (the decoherence

    problem). It is thus concluded that quantum theory is only relevant to physical

    processes in the (sub)atomic domain and should be ignored in other physical

    domains. However, there are many recent research developments suggesting that

    biological organisms at ordinary temperatures exploit subtle quantum effects, and

    biological evolution would thus have been able to solve the decoherence problem

    at least in some biological contexts (e.g. the studies on energy-harvesting in

    photosynthesis and avian magnetoreception; for a short review, see Ball, P.

    (2011)). As Atmanspacher points out, it is however still a controversial issue

    whether subtle quantum processes play a significant role in the neural correlates of

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    4/7

    4

    cognition and consciousness.

    Note that those researchers who accept that cognition is quantum-like and

    seek to explain this in neural terms need not necessarily adopt the program of

    strong quantum cognition. For there is also the possibility that the neural processes

    underlying cognition involve no subtle quantum effects, but can nevertheless give

    rise to quantum-like neural activity. Something like this is implied by Barros and

    Suppes (2009) when they suggest that classicalinterference in the brain may lead

    to contextual processes. They refer to experimental work according to which

    cortical oscillations may propagate in the cortex as if they were waves; and to

    simulations of the mammalian brain which show the presence of interference in

    the cortex.

    3. Bohmian programmes of quantum cognition

    We already mentioned briefly above that the physicist David Bohm speculated

    early about strong quantum cognition in his 1951 textbook. At that time he was

    thinking within the usual interpretation of quantum theory, and the analogies he

    drew attention to then reflect this. As is well known, Bohms key long-term aim

    was to understand quantum theory better, and this led him to develop a number of

    different alternative schemes. Given his early intuition that quantum theory and

    thought are analogous, it is not surprising that he applied the new ideas arising

    from his various quantum schemes to describing the mind.

    In 1952 Bohm published two articles inPhysical Review where he proposed

    (following deBroglies earlier ideas) that an electron is a particle guided by a field.

    In later work with Basil Hiley, Bohm emphasized that this field does not push andpull the particle mechanically but rather in-forms its energy. Thus, Bohm and

    Hiley argued, the key new ontological feature of quantum theory is the existence

    of objective and active information at the quantum level. Bohm extended this

    model to include higher-levels of information, so that cognitive informational

    processes could be connected to quantum information, which in turn could control

    neurophysiological processes in, say, synapses. This line of research has been

    developed by e.g. Pylkknen and Hiley. They propose that the approach enables

    new ways of understanding such key philosophical problems as mental causation,

    intentionality and even consciousness.

    In Bohms active information scheme it is assumed that quantum theory

    needs to be extended into a hierarchy of levels of active information, where the

    human mind, for example, involves not only the lower levels, but also the more

    subtle levels (Bohm claimed that such an extension of quantum theory is not

    arbitrary, but natural from the physical and mathematical point of view). Some

    of these levels are at the manifest, classical level while others are more subtle.

    In perception, information encoded in manifest levels (e.g. in the form of printed

    words) is carried toward the more subtle levels in the nervous system, where the

    meaning of the information is apprehended. Such apprehension of meaning is an

    activity, which crucially involves the organization of the lower levels of

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    5/7

    5

    information. There is thus a two-way traffic between manifest and subtle levels.

    It is in this way that we can understand how mind (understood as involving very

    subtle physical levels) can influence the more manifest aspects of the physical

    domain (e.g. the movement of the hand). In other words, we obtain a new way of

    understanding mental causation.

    One key idea is that the more subtle, physical (mental) levels are

    influenced by and can also influence the lower, manifest levels. Mind is not

    floating free from the quantum and classical levels, but can influence these latter,

    thus providing a new way of understanding mental causation. The level of

    quantum information is especially important in providing the missing link between

    the traditional categories of physical and mental. Of course, it is a major unsolved

    problem in the Bohm scheme what exactly is meant by the subtle levels. It

    seems that Bohm meant both complex neurophysiological processes (alreadydescribed in cognitive neuroscience), and some subtle quantum and super-

    quantum effects taking place in the brain but not yet discovered. Thus this is

    currently a heavily speculative scheme which needs much further critical

    examination and development. Yet, in my view, it has some advantages over the

    other schemes of strong quantum cognition (see Hiley & Pylkknen 2005). It can

    be argued that the Bohm-Hiley ontological interpretation provides currently the

    best ontological scheme for quantum theory, and we need a clear quantum

    ontology to tackle in a quantum-theoretical way the mind-matter problem, also

    known as the ontological problem (Churchland 2013).

    In the early 1960s Bohm began to seek a more general scheme in which

    one could bring quantum theory and relativity together. This framework became

    known as the implicate order. The implicate order refers to holistic phenomena,where, for example, information about the whole is enfolded in each region (as in

    the movement of lights waves, which can be recorded in a hologram). Applied to

    the universe, this suggests that the universe is a movement in which a holistic

    order, the implicate order prevails thus the universe is holomovement. At each

    moment a three-dimensional explicate order unfolds from the holomovement, only

    to enfold back in the next moment. This process of unfoldment and enfoldment

    takes place so rapidly that we do not see it but instead typically perceive an

    enduring three-dimensional reality of macroscopic objects.

    Bohm proposed that the implicate order is fundamental and general, and

    also prevails in biological and psychological phenomena. For example, the

    conscious experience of listening to music can be understood in terms of the

    implicate order. A symphony involves a movement in which a total order builds

    up and grows. At each moment we are most explicitly aware of certain tones,

    while the previously explicate tones are experienced as enfolded, actively

    transforming structures; our experience also involves an anticipation the future

    tones. Bohm thus provided a new way of thinking and modeling a central issue in

    phenomenology, namely time consciousness. This has been discussed in some

    detail by Pylkknen (2007, ch 5). Such an application of the implicate order to

    describe phenomenal experience can be seen as an instance of weak quantum

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    6/7

    6

    cognition, as one is using a theoretical scheme inspired by quantum theory while

    not claiming that phenomenal experience is literally a quantum phenomenon.

    4. Discussion

    Strong programs of quantum cognition typically underline the importance of

    physical considerations when trying to understand they mind. However, this need

    not imply the assumption that mental processes are reduced to some quantum

    mechanical processes. []

    References

    Aerts, D. Quantum structure in cognition, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 53

    (2009) 314-348.

    Atmanspacher, Harald, (2011) Quantum Approaches to Consciousness, The

    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =

    Atmanspacher, H., Rmer, H., and Walach, H. (2002). Weak quantum theory:

    Complementarity and entanglement in physics and beyond. Foundations of

    Physics 32, 379406.

    Ball, P. (2011) The dawn of quantum biology,Nature 474, pp. 272-274).

    Barros, J.A. & Suppes, P. Quantum mechanics, interference and the brain, Journal

    of Mathematical Psychology 53 (2009) 306-313.

    Churchland, P. (2013) Matter and Consciousness. 3rd edition. Cambridge,

    Mass.:MI TPress.

    Globus, G. (2003) Quantum Closures and Disclosures: Thinking-together

    postphenomenology and quantum brain dynamics. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Pothos, M & Busemeyer J. R. (2013) Can quantum probability provide a new

    direction for cognitive modeling?Behavioral and Brain Science

    Pylkknen, P. (2004) Can quantum analogies help us to understand the process of

    thought?, in G. Globus, K. Pribram and G. Vitiello (eds.) Being and Brain. At the

    Boundary between Science, Philosophy, Language and Arts, pp. 167-197.

    Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

  • 7/27/2019 ICCN_Pylkkanen_paper 2013-10-24.doc

    7/7

    7